Old unstaged changes
I hope these are mostly non dangerous. Looks like it's mainly some reformatting.
This commit is contained in:
parent
6f275247dd
commit
188bba6c8d
|
@ -3,22 +3,21 @@ The usual notion of propositional equality in intensional type-theory
|
||||||
is restrictive. For instance it does not admit functional
|
is restrictive. For instance it does not admit functional
|
||||||
extensionality nor univalence. This poses a severe limitation on both
|
extensionality nor univalence. This poses a severe limitation on both
|
||||||
what is \emph{provable} and the \emph{re-usability} of proofs. Recent
|
what is \emph{provable} and the \emph{re-usability} of proofs. Recent
|
||||||
developments have however resulted in cubical type theory which
|
developments have, however, resulted in cubical type theory, which
|
||||||
permits a constructive proof of these two important notions. The
|
permits a constructive proof of univalence. The programming language
|
||||||
programming language Agda has been extended with capabilities for
|
Agda has been extended with capabilities for working in such a cubical
|
||||||
working in such a cubical setting. This thesis will explore the
|
setting. This thesis will explore the usefulness of this extension in
|
||||||
usefulness of this extension in the context of category theory.
|
the context of category theory.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
The thesis will motivate the need for univalence and explain why
|
The thesis will motivate the need for univalence and explain why
|
||||||
propositional equality in cubical Agda is more expressive than in
|
propositional equality in cubical Agda is more expressive than in
|
||||||
standard Agda. Alternative approaches to Cubical Agda will be
|
standard Agda. Alternative approaches to Cubical Agda will be
|
||||||
presented and their pros and cons will be explained. As an example of
|
presented and their pros and cons will be explained. As an example of
|
||||||
the application of univalence two formulations of monads will be
|
the application of univalence, two formulations of monads will be
|
||||||
presented: Namely monads in the monoidal form and monads in the
|
presented: Namely monads in the monoidal form and monads in the
|
||||||
Kleisli form and under the univalent interpretation it will be shown
|
Kleisli form. Using univalence, it will be shown how these are equal.
|
||||||
how these are equal.
|
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
Finally the thesis will explain the challenges that a developer will
|
Finally the thesis will explain the challenges that a developer will
|
||||||
face when working with cubical Agda and give some techniques to
|
face when working with cubical Agda and give some techniques to
|
||||||
overcome these difficulties. It will also try to suggest how further
|
overcome these difficulties. It will suggest how further work can
|
||||||
work can help alleviate some of these challenges.
|
help alleviate some of these challenges.
|
||||||
|
|
|
@ -12,27 +12,27 @@ thing Agda enjoys Uniqueness of Identity Proofs (UIP) though a flag
|
||||||
exists to turn this off. This feature is not present in Cubical Agda.
|
exists to turn this off. This feature is not present in Cubical Agda.
|
||||||
Rather than having unique identity proofs cubical Agda gives rise to a
|
Rather than having unique identity proofs cubical Agda gives rise to a
|
||||||
hierarchy of types with increasing \nomen{homotopical
|
hierarchy of types with increasing \nomen{homotopical
|
||||||
structure}{homotopy levels}. It turns out to be useful to built the
|
structure}{homotopy levels}. It turns out to be useful to build the
|
||||||
formalization with this hierarchy in mind as it can simplify proofs
|
formalization with this hierarchy in mind as it can simplify proofs
|
||||||
considerably. Another issue one must overcome in Cubical Agda is when
|
considerably. Another issue one must overcome in Cubical Agda is when
|
||||||
a type has a field whose type depends on a previous field. In this
|
a type has a field whose type depends on a previous field. In this
|
||||||
case paths between such types will be heterogeneous paths. In
|
case paths between such types will be heterogeneous paths. In
|
||||||
practice it turns out to be considerably more difficult to work with
|
practice it turns out to be considerably more difficult to work with
|
||||||
heterogeneous paths than with homogeneous paths. The thesis
|
heterogeneous paths than with homogeneous paths. This thesis
|
||||||
demonstrated the application of some techniques to overcome these
|
demonstrated the application of some techniques to overcome these
|
||||||
difficulties, such as based path induction.
|
difficulties, such as based path induction.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
This thesis formalizes some of the core concepts from category theory
|
This thesis formalizes some of the core concepts from category theory
|
||||||
including; categories, functors, products, exponentials, Cartesian
|
including: categories, functors, products, exponentials, Cartesian
|
||||||
closed categories, natural transformations, the yoneda embedding,
|
closed categories, natural transformations, the yoneda embedding,
|
||||||
monads and more. Category theory is an interesting case study for the
|
monads and more. Category theory is an interesting case study for the
|
||||||
application of cubical Agda for two reasons in particular: Because
|
application of cubical Agda for two reasons in particular. One reason
|
||||||
category theory is the study of abstract algebra of functions, meaning
|
is because category theory is the study of abstract algebra of
|
||||||
that functional extensionality is particularly relevant. Another
|
functions, meaning that functional extensionality is particularly
|
||||||
reason is that in category theory it is commonplace to identify
|
relevant. Another reason is that in category theory it is commonplace
|
||||||
isomorphic structures. Univalence allows for making this notion
|
to identify isomorphic structures. Univalence allows for making this
|
||||||
precise. This thesis also demonstrated another technique that is
|
notion precise. This thesis also demonstrated another technique that
|
||||||
common in category theory; namely to define categories to prove
|
is common in category theory; namely to define categories to prove
|
||||||
properties of other structures. Specifically a category was defined
|
properties of other structures. Specifically a category was defined
|
||||||
to demonstrate that any two product objects in a category are
|
to demonstrate that any two product objects in a category are
|
||||||
isomorphic. Furthermore the thesis showed two formulations of monads
|
isomorphic. Furthermore the thesis showed two formulations of monads
|
||||||
|
|
|
@ -7,7 +7,7 @@ $n$ simply by expanding the definition of $+$.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
On the other hand, propositional equality is something defined within
|
On the other hand, propositional equality is something defined within
|
||||||
the language itself. Propositional equality cannot be derived
|
the language itself. Propositional equality cannot be derived
|
||||||
automatically. The normal definition of judgmental equality is an
|
automatically. The normal definition of propositional equality is an
|
||||||
inductive data type. Cubical Agda discards this type in favor of some
|
inductive data type. Cubical Agda discards this type in favor of some
|
||||||
new primitives.
|
new primitives.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
@ -73,7 +73,7 @@ $$
|
||||||
p \tp \prod_{i \tp \I} P\ i
|
p \tp \prod_{i \tp \I} P\ i
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Which must satisfy being judgmentally equal to $a_0$ at the
|
This function must satisfy being judgmentally equal to $a_0$ at the
|
||||||
left endpoint and equal to $a_1$ at the other end. I.e.:
|
left endpoint and equal to $a_1$ at the other end. I.e.:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align*}
|
\begin{align*}
|
||||||
|
@ -93,8 +93,8 @@ I will generally prefer to use the notation $a \equiv b$ when talking
|
||||||
about non-dependent paths and use the notation $\Path\ (\lambda\; i
|
about non-dependent paths and use the notation $\Path\ (\lambda\; i
|
||||||
\to P\ i)\ a\ b$ when the path space is of particular interest.
|
\to P\ i)\ a\ b$ when the path space is of particular interest.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
With this definition we can also recover reflexivity. That is, for any $A \tp
|
With this definition we can recover reflexivity. That is, for any $A
|
||||||
\MCU$ and $a \tp A$:
|
\tp \MCU$ and $a \tp A$:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{equation}
|
\begin{equation}
|
||||||
\begin{aligned}
|
\begin{aligned}
|
||||||
|
@ -105,7 +105,7 @@ With this definition we can also recover reflexivity. That is, for any $A \tp
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Here the path space is $P \defeq \lambda\; i \to A$ and it satsifies
|
Here the path space is $P \defeq \lambda\; i \to A$ and it satsifies
|
||||||
$P\ i = A$ definitionally. So to inhabit it, is to give a path $\I \to
|
$P\ i = A$ definitionally. So to inhabit it, is to give a path $\I \to
|
||||||
A$ which is judgmentally $a$ at either endpoint. This is satisfied by
|
A$ that is judgmentally $a$ at either endpoint. This is satisfied by
|
||||||
the constant path; i.e.\ the path that is constantly $a$ at any index
|
the constant path; i.e.\ the path that is constantly $a$ at any index
|
||||||
$i \tp \I$.
|
$i \tp \I$.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
@ -120,14 +120,15 @@ Functional extensionality is the proposition that given a type $A \tp
|
||||||
\end{equation}
|
\end{equation}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
%% p = λ\; i a → p a i
|
%% p = λ\; i a → p a i
|
||||||
So given $η \tp \prod_{a \tp A} f\ a \equiv g\ a$ we must give a path $f \equiv
|
So given $η \tp \prod_{a \tp A} f\ a \equiv g\ a$ we must give a path
|
||||||
g$. That is a function $\I \to \prod_{a \tp A} B\ a$. So let $i \tp \I$ be given.
|
$f \equiv g$. That is a function $\I \to \prod_{a \tp A} B\ a$. So let
|
||||||
We must now give an expression $\phi \tp \prod_{a \tp A} B\ a$ satisfying
|
$i \tp \I$ be given. We must now give an expression $\phi \tp
|
||||||
$\phi\ 0 \equiv f\ a$ and $\phi\ 1 \equiv g\ a$. This neccesitates that the
|
\prod_{a \tp A} B\ a$ satisfying $\phi\ 0 \equiv f\ a$ and $\phi\ 1
|
||||||
expression must be a lambda-abstraction, so let $a \tp A$ be given. Now we can
|
\equiv g\ a$. This neccesitates that the expression must be a lambda
|
||||||
apply $a$ to $η$ and get the path $η\ a \tp f\ a \equiv g\ a$. And this exactly
|
abstraction, so let $a \tp A$ be given. We can now apply $a$ to $η$
|
||||||
satisfies the conditions for $\phi$. In conclustion \ref{eq:funExt} is inhabited
|
and get the path $η\ a \tp f\ a \equiv g\ a$. This exactly
|
||||||
by the term:
|
satisfies the conditions for $\phi$. In conclusion \ref{eq:funExt} is
|
||||||
|
inhabited by the term:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{equation*}
|
\begin{equation*}
|
||||||
\funExt\ η \defeq λ\; i\ a → η\ a\ i
|
\funExt\ η \defeq λ\; i\ a → η\ a\ i
|
||||||
|
@ -149,10 +150,10 @@ In ITT all equality proofs are identical (in a closed context). This
|
||||||
means that, in some sense, any two inhabitants of $a \equiv b$ are
|
means that, in some sense, any two inhabitants of $a \equiv b$ are
|
||||||
``equally good''. They do not have any interesting structure. This is
|
``equally good''. They do not have any interesting structure. This is
|
||||||
referred to as Uniqueness of Identity Proofs (UIP). Unfortunately it
|
referred to as Uniqueness of Identity Proofs (UIP). Unfortunately it
|
||||||
is not possible to have a type theory with both univalence and UIP. In
|
is not possible to have a type theory with both univalence and UIP.
|
||||||
stead in cubical Agda we have a hierarchy of types with an increasing
|
Instead in cubical Agda we have a hierarchy of types with an
|
||||||
amount of homotopic structure. At the bottom of this hierarchy is the
|
increasing amount of homotopic structure. At the bottom of this
|
||||||
set of contractible types:
|
hierarchy is the set of contractible types:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{equation}
|
\begin{equation}
|
||||||
\begin{aligned}
|
\begin{aligned}
|
||||||
|
@ -214,8 +215,8 @@ proving e.g.\ $\isProp\ \bN$ directly is not so straightforward (see
|
||||||
\cite[\S3.1.4]{hott-2013}). Hedberg's theorem states that any type
|
\cite[\S3.1.4]{hott-2013}). Hedberg's theorem states that any type
|
||||||
with decidable equality is a set. There will be examples of sets later
|
with decidable equality is a set. There will be examples of sets later
|
||||||
in this report. At this point it should be noted that the term ``set''
|
in this report. At this point it should be noted that the term ``set''
|
||||||
is somewhat conflated; there is the notion of sets from set-theory, in
|
is somewhat conflated; there is the notion of sets from set theory.
|
||||||
Agda types are denoted \texttt{Set}. I will use it consistently to
|
In Agda types are denoted \texttt{Set}. I will use it consistently to
|
||||||
refer to a type $A$ as a set exactly if $\isSet\ A$ is a proposition.
|
refer to a type $A$ as a set exactly if $\isSet\ A$ is a proposition.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
As the reader may have guessed the next step in the hierarchy is the type:
|
As the reader may have guessed the next step in the hierarchy is the type:
|
||||||
|
@ -227,11 +228,12 @@ As the reader may have guessed the next step in the hierarchy is the type:
|
||||||
\end{aligned}
|
\end{aligned}
|
||||||
\end{equation}
|
\end{equation}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
And so it continues. In fact we can generalize this family of types by indexing
|
So it continues. In fact we can generalize this family of types by
|
||||||
them with a natural number. For historical reasons, though, the bottom of the
|
indexing them with a natural number. For historical reasons, though,
|
||||||
hierarchy, the contractible types, is said to be a \nomen{-2-type}{homotopy
|
the bottom of the hierarchy, the contractible types, is said to be a
|
||||||
levels}, propositions are \nomen{-1-types}{homotopy levels}, (homotopical)
|
\nomen{-2-type}{homotopy levels}, propositions are
|
||||||
sets are \nomen{0-types}{homotopy levels} and so on\ldots
|
\nomen{-1-types}{homotopy levels}, (homotopical) sets are
|
||||||
|
\nomen{0-types}{homotopy levels} and so on\ldots
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
Just as with paths, homotopical sets are not at the center of focus for this
|
Just as with paths, homotopical sets are not at the center of focus for this
|
||||||
thesis. But I mention here some properties that will be relevant for this
|
thesis. But I mention here some properties that will be relevant for this
|
||||||
|
@ -250,7 +252,7 @@ Specifically the results come from the Agda library \texttt{cubical}
|
||||||
(\cite{cubical-demo}). I have used a handful of results from this
|
(\cite{cubical-demo}). I have used a handful of results from this
|
||||||
library as well as contributed a few lemmas myself%
|
library as well as contributed a few lemmas myself%
|
||||||
\footnote{The module \texttt{Cat.Prelude} lists the upstream
|
\footnote{The module \texttt{Cat.Prelude} lists the upstream
|
||||||
dependencies. As well my contribution to \texttt{cubical} can be
|
dependencies. My contribution to \texttt{cubical} can as well be
|
||||||
found in the git logs which are available at
|
found in the git logs which are available at
|
||||||
\hrefsymb{https://github.com/Saizan/cubical-demo}{\texttt{https://github.com/Saizan/cubical-demo}}.
|
\hrefsymb{https://github.com/Saizan/cubical-demo}{\texttt{https://github.com/Saizan/cubical-demo}}.
|
||||||
}.
|
}.
|
||||||
|
@ -279,12 +281,11 @@ $$
|
||||||
D \tp \prod_{b \tp A} \prod_{p \tp a ≡ b} \MCU
|
D \tp \prod_{b \tp A} \prod_{p \tp a ≡ b} \MCU
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
And an inhabitant of $D$ at $\refl$:
|
and an inhabitant of $D$ at $\refl$:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
d \tp D\ a\ \refl
|
d \tp D\ a\ \refl
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
%
|
|
||||||
We have the function:
|
We have the function:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{equation}
|
\begin{equation}
|
||||||
|
@ -343,7 +344,7 @@ over the family:
|
||||||
T\ d'\ r' & \defeq \trans\ p\ (\trans\ q\ r') ≡ \trans\ (\trans\ p\ q)\ r'
|
T\ d'\ r' & \defeq \trans\ p\ (\trans\ q\ r') ≡ \trans\ (\trans\ p\ q)\ r'
|
||||||
\end{align*}
|
\end{align*}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
So the base case is proven with $t$ which is defined as:
|
The base case is proven with $t$ which is defined as:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align*}
|
\begin{align*}
|
||||||
\trans\ p\ (\trans\ q\ \refl) & ≡
|
\trans\ p\ (\trans\ q\ \refl) & ≡
|
||||||
|
@ -376,7 +377,7 @@ $$
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Note that $d_0$ and $d_1$, though points of the same family, have
|
Note that $d_0$ and $d_1$, though points of the same family, have
|
||||||
different types. This is quite a mouthful. So let me try to show how
|
different types. This is quite a mouthful, so let me try to show how
|
||||||
this is a very general and useful result.
|
this is a very general and useful result.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
Often when proving equalities between elements of some dependent types
|
Often when proving equalities between elements of some dependent types
|
||||||
|
@ -388,7 +389,7 @@ $$
|
||||||
T \defeq \sum_{a \tp A} D\ a
|
T \defeq \sum_{a \tp A} D\ a
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
For some proposition $D \tp A \to \MCU$. That is we have $\var{propD}
|
for some proposition $D \tp A \to \MCU$. That is we have $\var{propD}
|
||||||
\tp \prod_{a \tp A} \isProp\ (D\ a)$. If we want to prove $t_0 \equiv
|
\tp \prod_{a \tp A} \isProp\ (D\ a)$. If we want to prove $t_0 \equiv
|
||||||
t_1$ for two elements $t_0, t_1 \tp T$ then this will be a pair of
|
t_1$ for two elements $t_0, t_1 \tp T$ then this will be a pair of
|
||||||
paths:
|
paths:
|
||||||
|
@ -408,7 +409,7 @@ $$
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\subsection{Functions over propositions}
|
\subsection{Functions over propositions}
|
||||||
\label{sec:propPi}
|
\label{sec:propPi}%
|
||||||
$\prod$-types preserve propositionality when the co-domain is always a
|
$\prod$-types preserve propositionality when the co-domain is always a
|
||||||
proposition.
|
proposition.
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
|
@ -419,7 +420,7 @@ $$
|
||||||
\label{sec:propSig}
|
\label{sec:propSig}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
$\sum$-types preserve propositionality whenever its first component is
|
$\sum$-types preserve propositionality whenever its first component is
|
||||||
a proposition, and its second component is a proposition for all
|
a proposition and its second component is a proposition for all
|
||||||
points of the left type.
|
points of the left type.
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
|
|
|
@ -10,8 +10,8 @@ mere propositions.
|
||||||
\subsection{Computational properties}
|
\subsection{Computational properties}
|
||||||
The new contribution of cubical Agda is that it has a constructive
|
The new contribution of cubical Agda is that it has a constructive
|
||||||
proof of functional extensionality\index{functional extensionality}
|
proof of functional extensionality\index{functional extensionality}
|
||||||
and univalence\index{univalence}. This means that in particular that
|
and univalence\index{univalence}. This means in particular that the
|
||||||
the type checker can reduce terms defined with these theorems. So one
|
type checker can reduce terms defined with these theorems. One
|
||||||
interesting result of this development is how much this influenced the
|
interesting result of this development is how much this influenced the
|
||||||
development. In particular having a functional extensionality that
|
development. In particular having a functional extensionality that
|
||||||
``computes'' should simplify some proofs.
|
``computes'' should simplify some proofs.
|
||||||
|
@ -33,24 +33,24 @@ module:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
I will not reproduce it in full here as the type is quite involved. In
|
I will not reproduce it in full here as the type is quite involved. In
|
||||||
stead I have put this in a source listing in \ref{app:abstract-funext}.
|
stead I have put this in a source listing in
|
||||||
The method used to find in what places the computational behaviour of
|
\ref{app:abstract-funext}. The method used to find in what places the
|
||||||
these proofs are needed has the caveat of only working for places that
|
computational behaviour of these proofs are needed has the caveat of
|
||||||
directly or transitively uses these two proofs. Fortunately though
|
only working for places that directly or transitively uses these two
|
||||||
the code is structured in such a way that this is the case. So in
|
proofs. Fortunately though the code is structured in such a way that
|
||||||
conclusion the way I have structured these proofs means that the
|
this is the case. In conclusion the way I have structured these proofs
|
||||||
computational behaviour of functional extensionality and univalence
|
means that the computational behaviour of functional extensionality
|
||||||
has not been so relevant.
|
and univalence has not been so relevant.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
Barring this the computational behaviour of paths can still be useful.
|
Barring this the computational behaviour of paths can still be useful.
|
||||||
E.g.\ if a programmer wants to reuse functions that operate on a
|
E.g.\ if a programmer wants to reuse functions that operate on a
|
||||||
monoidal monads to work with a monad in the Kleisli form that the
|
monoidal monads to work with a monad in the Kleisli form that the
|
||||||
programmer has specified. To make this idea concrete, say we are
|
programmer has specified. To make this idea concrete, say we are
|
||||||
given some function $f \tp \Kleisli \to T$ having a path between $p
|
given some function $f \tp \Kleisli \to T$, having a path between $p
|
||||||
\tp \Monoidal \equiv \Kleisli$ induces a map $\coe\ p \tp \Monoidal
|
\tp \Monoidal \equiv \Kleisli$ induces a map $\coe\ p \tp \Monoidal
|
||||||
\to \Kleisli$. We can compose $f$ with this map to get $f \comp
|
\to \Kleisli$. We can compose $f$ with this map to get $f \comp
|
||||||
\coe\ p \tp \Monoidal \to T$. Of course, since that map was
|
\coe\ p \tp \Monoidal \to T$. Of course, since that map was
|
||||||
constructed with an isomorphism these maps already exist and could be
|
constructed with an isomorphism, these maps already exist and could be
|
||||||
used directly. So this is arguably only interesting when one also
|
used directly. So this is arguably only interesting when one also
|
||||||
wants to prove properties of applying such functions.
|
wants to prove properties of applying such functions.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
|
|
@ -57,11 +57,11 @@ The concepts formalized in this development are:
|
||||||
\end{center}
|
\end{center}
|
||||||
\end{samepage}%
|
\end{samepage}%
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
As well as a range of various results about these. E.g.\ I have shown
|
I also provide a various results about these. E.g.\ I have shown that
|
||||||
that the category of sets has products. In the following I aim to
|
the category of sets has products. In the following I aim to
|
||||||
demonstrate some of the techniques employed in this formalization and
|
demonstrate some of the techniques employed in this formalization.
|
||||||
in the interest of brevity I will not detail all the things I have
|
In the interest of brevity I will not detail all the things I have
|
||||||
formalized. In stead I have selected parts of this formalization that
|
formalized. Instead I have selected parts of this formalization that
|
||||||
highlight some interesting proof techniques relevant to doing proofs
|
highlight some interesting proof techniques relevant to doing proofs
|
||||||
in Cubical Agda. This chapter will focus on the definition of
|
in Cubical Agda. This chapter will focus on the definition of
|
||||||
\emph{categories}, \emph{equivalences}, the \emph{opposite category},
|
\emph{categories}, \emph{equivalences}, the \emph{opposite category},
|
||||||
|
@ -82,15 +82,15 @@ mathematical way'', where one can reason about two categories by
|
||||||
simply focusing on the data. This is achieved by creating a function
|
simply focusing on the data. This is achieved by creating a function
|
||||||
embodying the equality principle for a given type.
|
embodying the equality principle for a given type.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
For the rest of this chapter I will present some of these results. For
|
For the rest of this chapter I will present some of these results.
|
||||||
didactic reasons no source-code has been included in this chapter. To
|
For didactic reasons no source-code has been included in this chapter.
|
||||||
see the formal definitions the reader is referred to the
|
To see the formal definitions the reader is referred to the
|
||||||
implementation which is linked in the tables above.
|
implementation which is linked in the tables above.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\section{Categories}
|
\section{Categories}
|
||||||
\label{sec:categories}
|
\label{sec:categories}
|
||||||
The data for a category consist of a type for the sort of objects; a
|
The data for a category consist of a type for the sort of objects, a
|
||||||
type for the sort of arrows; an identity arrow and a composition
|
type for the sort of arrows, an identity arrow and a composition
|
||||||
operation for arrows. Another record encapsulates some laws about
|
operation for arrows. Another record encapsulates some laws about
|
||||||
this data: associativity of composition, identity law for the identity
|
this data: associativity of composition, identity law for the identity
|
||||||
morphism. These are standard constituents of a category and can be
|
morphism. These are standard constituents of a category and can be
|
||||||
|
@ -98,17 +98,18 @@ found in typical mathematical expositions on the topic. We shall
|
||||||
impose one further requirement on what it means to be a category,
|
impose one further requirement on what it means to be a category,
|
||||||
namely that the type of arrows form a set.
|
namely that the type of arrows form a set.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
Such categories are called \nomen{1-categories}{1-category}. It is
|
Categories whose type of arrows form a set are called
|
||||||
possible to relax this requirement. This would lead to the notion of
|
\nomen{1-categories}{1-category}. It is possible to relax this
|
||||||
higher categories (\cite[p. 307]{hott-2013}). For the purpose of this
|
requirement. This would lead to the notion of higher categories
|
||||||
thesis however, this report will restrict itself to
|
(\cite[p. 307]{hott-2013}). However this thesis will restrict itself
|
||||||
1-categories\index{1-category}. Generalizing this work to higher
|
to 1-categories\index{1-category}. Generalizing this work to higher
|
||||||
categories would be a very natural extension of this work.
|
categories would be a very natural extension of this work.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
Raw categories satisfying all of the above requirements are called a
|
Raw categories satisfying all of the above requirements are called a
|
||||||
\nomenindex{pre-categories}. As a further requirement to be a proper category we
|
\nomenindex{pre-categories}. As a further requirement to be a proper
|
||||||
require it to be univalent. Before we can define this, I must introduce two more
|
category we require the arrows to be univalent. Before we can define
|
||||||
definitions: If we let $p$ be a witness to the identity law, which formally is:
|
this, I must introduce two additional definitions: If we let $p$ be a
|
||||||
|
witness to the identity law, which formally is:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{equation}
|
\begin{equation}
|
||||||
\label{eq:identity}
|
\label{eq:identity}
|
||||||
|
@ -118,20 +119,20 @@ definitions: If we let $p$ be a witness to the identity law, which formally is:
|
||||||
\end{equation}
|
\end{equation}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Then we can construct the identity isomorphism $\idIso \tp (\identity,
|
Then we can construct the identity isomorphism $\idIso \tp (\identity,
|
||||||
\identity, p) \tp A ≊ A$ for any object $A$. Here $≊$
|
\identity, p) \tp A ≊ A$ for any object $A$. Here $≊$ denotes
|
||||||
denotes isomorphism on objects (whereas $\cong$ denotes isomorphism on
|
isomorphism on objects (whereas $\cong$ denotes isomorphism on types).
|
||||||
types). This will be elaborated further on in sections
|
This will be elaborated further on in sections \S\ref{sec:equiv} and
|
||||||
\S\ref{sec:equiv} and \S\ref{sec:univalence}. Moreover due to
|
\S\ref{sec:univalence}. Moreover due to substitution for paths we can
|
||||||
substitution for paths we can construct an isomorphism from \emph{any}
|
construct an isomorphism from \emph{any} path:
|
||||||
path:
|
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{equation}
|
\begin{equation}
|
||||||
\idToIso \tp A ≡ B → A ≊ B
|
\idToIso \tp A ≡ B → A ≊ B
|
||||||
\end{equation}
|
\end{equation}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
The univalence criterion for categories states that this map must be an
|
The univalence criterion for categories states that $\idToIso$ must be
|
||||||
equivalence. The requirement is similar to univalence for types, but where
|
an equivalence. The requirement is similar to univalence for types,
|
||||||
isomorphism on objects play the role of equivalence on types. Formally:
|
but where isomorphism on objects play the role of equivalence on
|
||||||
|
types. Formally:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
\label{eq:cat-univ}
|
\label{eq:cat-univ}
|
||||||
|
@ -146,10 +147,10 @@ Note that \ref{eq:cat-univ} is \emph{not} the same as:
|
||||||
(A ≡ B) ≃ (A ≊ B)
|
(A ≡ B) ≃ (A ≊ B)
|
||||||
\end{equation}
|
\end{equation}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
However the two are logically equivalent: One can construct the latter
|
However the two are logically equivalent: one can construct the latter
|
||||||
from the former simply by ``forgetting'' that $\idToIso$ plays the
|
from the former simply by ``forgetting'' that $\idToIso$ plays the
|
||||||
role of the equivalence. The other direction is more involved and will
|
role of the equivalence. The other direction is more involved and
|
||||||
be discussed in section \S\ref{sec:univalence}.
|
will be discussed in section \S\ref{sec:univalence}.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
In summary the definition of a category is the following collection of
|
In summary the definition of a category is the following collection of
|
||||||
data:
|
data:
|
||||||
|
@ -161,7 +162,7 @@ data:
|
||||||
\lll & \tp \Arrow\ B\ C → \Arrow\ A\ B → \Arrow\ A\ C
|
\lll & \tp \Arrow\ B\ C → \Arrow\ A\ B → \Arrow\ A\ C
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
And laws:
|
and laws:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
%% \tag{associativity}
|
%% \tag{associativity}
|
||||||
|
@ -182,16 +183,16 @@ And laws:
|
||||||
\isEquiv\ (A ≡ B)\ (A ≊ B)\ \idToIso
|
\isEquiv\ (A ≡ B)\ (A ≊ B)\ \idToIso
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
The function $\lll$ denotes arrow composition (right-to-left), and
|
The function $\lll$ denotes arrow composition (right-to-left) and
|
||||||
reverse function composition (left-to-right, diagrammatic order) is
|
reverse function composition (left-to-right, diagrammatic order) is
|
||||||
denoted $\rrr$. The objects ($A$, $B$ and $C$) and arrow ($f$, $g$,
|
denoted $\rrr$. The objects ($A$, $B$ and $C$) and arrows ($f$, $g$,
|
||||||
$h$) are implicitly universally quantified.
|
$h$) are implicitly universally quantified.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
With all this in place it is now possible to prove that all the laws
|
With all this in place it is now possible to prove that all the laws
|
||||||
are indeed mere propositions. Most of the proofs simply use the fact
|
are indeed mere propositions. Most of the proofs simply use the fact
|
||||||
that the type of arrows are sets. This is because most of the laws are
|
that the type of arrows are sets. This is because most of the laws are
|
||||||
a collection of equations between arrows in the category. And since
|
a collection of equations between arrows in the category. And since
|
||||||
such a proof does not have any content exactly because the type of
|
such a proof does not have any content, exactly because the type of
|
||||||
arrows form a set, two witnesses must be the same. All the proofs are
|
arrows form a set, two witnesses must be the same. All the proofs are
|
||||||
really quite mechanical. Let us have a look at one of them: Proving
|
really quite mechanical. Let us have a look at one of them: Proving
|
||||||
that \ref{eq:identity} is a mere proposition:
|
that \ref{eq:identity} is a mere proposition:
|
||||||
|
@ -217,10 +218,10 @@ $$
|
||||||
\isProp\ \left( \left( \id \comp f ≡ f \right) \x \left( f \comp \id ≡ f \right) \right)
|
\isProp\ \left( \left( \id \comp f ≡ f \right) \x \left( f \comp \id ≡ f \right) \right)
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Then we eliminate the (non-dependent) sigma-type by applying $\propSig$ giving
|
We then eliminate the (non-dependent) sigma-type by applying
|
||||||
us the two obligations $\isProp\ (\id \comp f ≡ f)$ and $\isProp\ (f \comp
|
$\propSig$ giving us the two obligations $\isProp\ (\id \comp f ≡ f)$
|
||||||
\id ≡ f)$ which follows from the type of arrows being a
|
and $\isProp\ (f \comp \id ≡ f)$ which follows from the type of arrows
|
||||||
set.
|
being a set.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
This example illustrates nicely how we can use these combinators to
|
This example illustrates nicely how we can use these combinators to
|
||||||
reason about `canonical' types like $∑$ and $∏$. Similar
|
reason about `canonical' types like $∑$ and $∏$. Similar
|
||||||
|
@ -246,7 +247,7 @@ Where the definition of $\IsPreCategory$ is the triple:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Each corresponding to the first three laws for categories. Note that
|
Each corresponding to the first three laws for categories. Note that
|
||||||
since $\IsPreCategory$ is not formulated with a chain of sigma-types
|
since $\IsPreCategory$ is not formulated with a chain of sigma-types
|
||||||
we will not have any combinators available to help us here. In stead
|
we will not have any combinators available to help us here. Instead
|
||||||
the path type must be used directly.
|
the path type must be used directly.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
The type \ref{eq:propIsPreCategory} is judgmentally the same as:
|
The type \ref{eq:propIsPreCategory} is judgmentally the same as:
|
||||||
|
@ -255,13 +256,13 @@ $$
|
||||||
∏_{a, b \tp \IsPreCategory} a ≡ b
|
∏_{a, b \tp \IsPreCategory} a ≡ b
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
So to prove the proposition let $a, b \tp \IsPreCategory$ be given. To
|
To prove the proposition let $a, b \tp \IsPreCategory$ be given. To
|
||||||
prove the equality $a ≡ b$ is to give a continuous path from the
|
prove the equality $a ≡ b$ is to give a continuous path from the
|
||||||
index-type into the path-space. I.e.\ a function $\I →
|
index-type into the path space; i.e.\ a function $\I →
|
||||||
\IsPreCategory$. This path must satisfy being being judgmentally the
|
\IsPreCategory$. This path must satisfy being being judgmentally the
|
||||||
same as $a$ at the left endpoint and $b$ at the right endpoint. We
|
same as $a$ at the left endpoint and $b$ at the right endpoint. We
|
||||||
know we can form a continuous path between all projections of $a$ and
|
know we can form a continuous path between all projections of $a$ and
|
||||||
$b$, this follows from the type of all the projections being mere
|
$b$. This follows from the type of all the projections being mere
|
||||||
propositions. For instance, the path between $a.\isIdentity$ and
|
propositions. For instance, the path between $a.\isIdentity$ and
|
||||||
$b.\isIdentity$ is simply formed by:
|
$b.\isIdentity$ is simply formed by:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
|
@ -271,14 +272,15 @@ $$
|
||||||
a.\isIdentity ≡ b.\isIdentity
|
a.\isIdentity ≡ b.\isIdentity
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
So to give the continuous function $\I → \IsPreCategory$, which is our goal, we
|
To give the continuous function $\I → \IsPreCategory$, which is our
|
||||||
introduce $i \tp \I$ and proceed by constructing an element of $\IsPreCategory$
|
goal, we introduce $i \tp \I$ and proceed by constructing an element
|
||||||
by using the fact that all the projections are propositions to generate paths
|
of $\IsPreCategory$ by using the fact that all the projections are
|
||||||
between all projections. Once we have such a path e.g.\ $p \tp a.\isIdentity
|
propositions to generate paths between all projections. Once we have
|
||||||
≡ b.\isIdentity$ we can eliminate it with $i$ and thus obtain $p\ i \tp
|
such a path e.g.\ $p \tp a.\isIdentity ≡ b.\isIdentity$ we can
|
||||||
(p\ i).\isIdentity$. This element satisfies exactly that it corresponds to the
|
eliminate it with $i$ and thus obtain $p\ i \tp (p\ i).\isIdentity$.
|
||||||
corresponding projections at either endpoint. Thus the element we construct at
|
This element satisfies exactly that it corresponds to the
|
||||||
$i$ becomes the triple:
|
corresponding projections at either endpoint. Thus the element we
|
||||||
|
construct at $i$ becomes the triple:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{equation}
|
\begin{equation}
|
||||||
\label{eq:proof-prop-IsPreCategory}
|
\label{eq:proof-prop-IsPreCategory}
|
||||||
|
@ -296,7 +298,7 @@ I have found this to be a general pattern when proving things in
|
||||||
homotopy type theory, namely that you have to wrap and unwrap
|
homotopy type theory, namely that you have to wrap and unwrap
|
||||||
equalities at different levels. It is worth noting that proving this
|
equalities at different levels. It is worth noting that proving this
|
||||||
theorem with the regular inductive equality type would already not be
|
theorem with the regular inductive equality type would already not be
|
||||||
possible, since we at least need functional
|
possible since we at least need functional
|
||||||
extensionality\index{functional extensionality} (the projections are
|
extensionality\index{functional extensionality} (the projections are
|
||||||
all $∏$-types). Assuming we had functional extensionality available to
|
all $∏$-types). Assuming we had functional extensionality available to
|
||||||
us as an axiom, we would use functional extensionality to retrieve the
|
us as an axiom, we would use functional extensionality to retrieve the
|
||||||
|
@ -307,9 +309,9 @@ a~priori that equality proofs are unique.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
The situation is a bit more complicated when we have a dependent type.
|
The situation is a bit more complicated when we have a dependent type.
|
||||||
For instance when we want to show that $\IsCategory$ is a mere
|
For instance when we want to show that $\IsCategory$ is a mere
|
||||||
proposition. The type $\IsCategory$ is a record with two fields, a
|
proposition. The type $\IsCategory$ is a record with two fields: a
|
||||||
witness of being a pre-category and the univalence condition. Recall
|
witness of being a pre-category and the univalence condition. Recall
|
||||||
that the univalence condition is indexed by the identity-proof. So to
|
that the univalence condition is indexed by the identity-proof. To
|
||||||
follow the same recipe as above, let $a, b \tp \IsCategory$ be given,
|
follow the same recipe as above, let $a, b \tp \IsCategory$ be given,
|
||||||
to show them equal, we now need to give two paths. One homogeneous:
|
to show them equal, we now need to give two paths. One homogeneous:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
|
@ -332,13 +334,13 @@ result that univalence is a proposition to a heterogeneous path. To
|
||||||
this end we can use $\lemPropF$, which was introduced in
|
this end we can use $\lemPropF$, which was introduced in
|
||||||
\S\ref{sec:lemPropF}.
|
\S\ref{sec:lemPropF}.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
In this case $A = \var{IsIdentity}\ \identity$ and $B =
|
Looking at the definition of $\lemPropF$ we have that $A =
|
||||||
\Univalent$. We have shown that being a category is a proposition, a
|
\var{IsIdentity}\ \identity$ and $D = \Univalent$ to give the path at
|
||||||
result that holds for any choice of identity proof so it will also
|
hand. We have shown that being a category is a proposition, a result
|
||||||
hold for the witness obtained at an arbitrary point along $p$. Finally
|
that holds for any choice of identity proof so it will also hold for
|
||||||
we must provide a proof that the identity proofs at $a$ and $b$ are
|
the witness obtained at an arbitrary point along $p$. Finally we must
|
||||||
indeed the same, this we can extract from $p$ by applying congruence
|
provide a proof that the identity proofs at $a$ and $b$ are indeed the
|
||||||
of paths:
|
same, this we can extract from $p$ by applying congruence of paths:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
\congruence\ \isIdentity\ p
|
\congruence\ \isIdentity\ p
|
||||||
|
@ -350,10 +352,10 @@ $$
|
||||||
\var{lemPropF}\ \var{propUnivalent}\ (\var{cong}\ p.\var{isIdentity})
|
\var{lemPropF}\ \var{propUnivalent}\ (\var{cong}\ p.\var{isIdentity})
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
And this finishes the proof that being-a-category is a mere proposition
|
This finishes the proof that being-a-category is a mere proposition
|
||||||
(\ref{eq:propIsPreCategory}).
|
(\ref{eq:propIsPreCategory}).
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
When we have a proper category we can make precise the notion of
|
When we have a proper category, we can make precise the notion of
|
||||||
``identifying isomorphic types''. That is, we can construct the
|
``identifying isomorphic types''. That is, we can construct the
|
||||||
function:
|
function:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
|
@ -395,8 +397,8 @@ $\Isomorphism\ f$. This also gives rise to the following type:
|
||||||
A \cong B ≜ ∑_{f \tp A → B} \Isomorphism\ f
|
A \cong B ≜ ∑_{f \tp A → B} \Isomorphism\ f
|
||||||
\end{equation}
|
\end{equation}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
At the same place \cite{hott-2013} gives an ``interface'' for what the judgment
|
At the same place \cite{hott-2013} gives an ``interface'' for what
|
||||||
$\isEquiv \tp (A → B) → \MCU$ must provide:
|
the judgment $\isEquiv \tp (A → B) → \MCU$ must provide:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
\var{fromIso} & \tp \Isomorphism\ f → \isEquiv\ f \\
|
\var{fromIso} & \tp \Isomorphism\ f → \isEquiv\ f \\
|
||||||
|
@ -465,7 +467,7 @@ As mentioned the univalence criterion for some category $\bC$ says that for all
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
\isEquiv\ (A ≡ B)\ (A ≊ B)\ \idToIso
|
\isEquiv\ (A ≡ B)\ (A ≊ B)\ \idToIso
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
And I mentioned that this was logically equivalent to
|
This is logically equivalent to
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
(A ≡ B) ≃ (A ≊ B)
|
(A ≡ B) ≃ (A ≊ B)
|
||||||
|
@ -484,10 +486,10 @@ dwell on this for a few seconds. This type looks very similar to
|
||||||
univalence for types and is therefore perhaps a bit more intuitive to
|
univalence for types and is therefore perhaps a bit more intuitive to
|
||||||
grasp the implications of. Of course univalence for types (which is a
|
grasp the implications of. Of course univalence for types (which is a
|
||||||
theorem -- i.e.\ provably holds) does not imply univalence of all
|
theorem -- i.e.\ provably holds) does not imply univalence of all
|
||||||
pre-category since morphisms in a category are not regular functions
|
pre-category since morphisms in a category are not regular functions,
|
||||||
-- in stead they can be thought of as a generalization hereof. The
|
instead they can be thought of as a generalization hereof. The
|
||||||
univalence criterion therefore is simply a way of restricting arrows
|
univalence criterion therefore is simply a way of restricting arrows
|
||||||
to behave like maps with respect to univalence.
|
to behave like regular functions with respects to paths.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
I will now mention a few helpful theorems that follow from univalence that will
|
I will now mention a few helpful theorems that follow from univalence that will
|
||||||
become useful later.
|
become useful later.
|
||||||
|
@ -554,7 +556,7 @@ are trying to prove but talks about paths rather than isomorphisms:
|
||||||
Again $p_{\var{dom}}$ denotes the path $\Arrow\ A\ X ≡ \Arrow\ B\ X$
|
Again $p_{\var{dom}}$ denotes the path $\Arrow\ A\ X ≡ \Arrow\ B\ X$
|
||||||
induced by $p$. To prove this statement let $f$ and $p$ be given then
|
induced by $p$. To prove this statement let $f$ and $p$ be given then
|
||||||
we invoke based path induction. The induction will be based at $A \tp
|
we invoke based path induction. The induction will be based at $A \tp
|
||||||
\Object$ Let $\widetilde{B} \tp \Object$ and $\widetilde{p} \tp A ≡
|
\Object$. Let $\widetilde{B} \tp \Object$ and $\widetilde{p} \tp A ≡
|
||||||
\widetilde{B}$ be given. The family that we perform induction over
|
\widetilde{B}$ be given. The family that we perform induction over
|
||||||
will be:
|
will be:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
|
@ -590,28 +592,30 @@ term:
|
||||||
\pathJ\ D\ d\ B\ p
|
\pathJ\ D\ d\ B\ p
|
||||||
\end{equation}
|
\end{equation}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
And this finishes the proof of \ref{eq:coeDomIso} and thus \ref{eq:coeDom}.
|
This finishes the proof of \ref{eq:coeDomIso} and thus
|
||||||
|
\ref{eq:coeDom}.
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\section{Categories}
|
\section{Categories}
|
||||||
\subsection{Opposite category}
|
\subsection{Opposite category}
|
||||||
\label{op-cat}
|
\label{op-cat}
|
||||||
The first category I will present is a pure construction on categories. Given
|
The first category I will present is a pure construction on
|
||||||
some category we can construct its dual, called the opposite category. Starting
|
categories. Given some category we can construct its dual, called the
|
||||||
with a simple example allows us to focus on how we work with equivalences and
|
opposite category. Starting with a simple example allows us to focus
|
||||||
univalence in a very simple category where the structure of the category is
|
on how we work with equivalences and univalence rather than being
|
||||||
rather simple.
|
distracted by some intricate structure of the category.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
Let $\bC$ be some category, we then define the opposite category
|
Let $\bC$ be some category, we then define the opposite category
|
||||||
$\bC^{\var{Op}}$. It has the same objects, but the type of arrows are flipped,
|
$\bC^{\var{Op}}$. It has the same objects, but the type of arrows are
|
||||||
that is to say an arrow from $A$ to $B$ in the opposite category corresponds to
|
flipped, that is to say an arrow from $A$ to $B$ in the opposite
|
||||||
an arrow from $B$ to $A$ in the underlying category. The identity arrow is the
|
category corresponds to an arrow from $B$ to $A$ in the underlying
|
||||||
same as the one in the underlying category (they have the same type). Function
|
category. The identity arrow is the same as the one in the underlying
|
||||||
composition will be reverse function composition from the underlying category.
|
category (they have the same type). Function composition will be
|
||||||
|
reverse function composition from the underlying category.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
I will refer to things in terms of the underlying category, unless they have an
|
I will refer to things in terms of the underlying category unless they
|
||||||
over-bar. So e.g.\ $\idToIso$ is a function in the underlying category and the
|
have a line above them. E.g.\ $\idToIso$ is a function in the
|
||||||
corresponding thing is denoted $\wideoverbar{\idToIso}$ in the opposite
|
underlying category and the corresponding thing is denoted
|
||||||
category.
|
$\wideoverbar{\idToIso}$ in the opposite category.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
Showing that this forms a pre-category is rather straightforward.
|
Showing that this forms a pre-category is rather straightforward.
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
|
@ -628,9 +632,9 @@ $$
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
This is just the swapped version of identity.
|
This is just the swapped version of identity.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
Finally, that the arrows form sets just follows by flipping the order of the
|
Finally, that the arrows form sets just follows by flipping the order
|
||||||
arguments. Or in other words; since $\Arrow\ A\ B$ is a set for all $A\;B \tp
|
of the arguments. Or in other words: since $\Arrow\ A\ B$ is a set
|
||||||
\Object$ then so is $Arrow\ B\ A$.
|
for all $A\;B \tp \Object$ then so is $Arrow\ B\ A$.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
Now, to show that this category is univalent is not as straightforward. Luckily
|
Now, to show that this category is univalent is not as straightforward. Luckily
|
||||||
section \S\ref{sec:equiv} gave us some tools to work with equivalences. We saw
|
section \S\ref{sec:equiv} gave us some tools to work with equivalences. We saw
|
||||||
|
@ -649,9 +653,9 @@ opposite direction. I name these maps $\shufflef \tp (A ≊ B) → (A
|
||||||
\wideoverbar{≊} B)$ and $\shufflef^{-1} \tp (A \wideoverbar{≊} B) → (A
|
\wideoverbar{≊} B)$ and $\shufflef^{-1} \tp (A \wideoverbar{≊} B) → (A
|
||||||
≊ B)$ respectively.
|
≊ B)$ respectively.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
As the inverse of $\wideoverbar{\idToIso}$ I will pick $\wideoverbar{\isoToId}
|
As the inverse of $\wideoverbar{\idToIso}$ I will pick
|
||||||
≜ \isoToId \comp \shufflef$. The proof that they are inverses go as
|
$\wideoverbar{\isoToId} ≜ \isoToId \comp \shufflef$. The proof that
|
||||||
follows:
|
they are inverses goes as follows:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align*}
|
\begin{align*}
|
||||||
\wideoverbar{\isoToId} \comp \wideoverbar{\idToIso} & =
|
\wideoverbar{\isoToId} \comp \wideoverbar{\idToIso} & =
|
||||||
|
@ -673,13 +677,15 @@ follows:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
The other direction is analogous.
|
The other direction is analogous.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
The lemma used in step 2 of this proof states that $\wideoverbar{idToIso} ≡
|
The lemma used in step 2 of this proof states that
|
||||||
\inv{\shufflef} \comp \idToIso$. This is a rather straightforward proof
|
$\wideoverbar{idToIso} ≡ \inv{\shufflef} \comp \idToIso$. This is a
|
||||||
since being-an-inverse-of is a proposition, so it suffices to show that their
|
rather straightforward proof since being-an-inverse-of is a
|
||||||
first components are equal, but this holds judgmentally.
|
proposition, so it suffices to show that their first components are
|
||||||
|
equal but this holds judgmentally.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
This finished the proof that the opposite category is in fact a category. Now,
|
This concludes the proof that the opposite category is in fact a
|
||||||
to prove that opposite-of is an involution we must show:
|
category. Now, to prove that opposite-of is an involution we must
|
||||||
|
show:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
∏_{\bC \tp \Category} \left(\bC^{\var{Op}}\right)^{\var{Op}} ≡ \bC
|
∏_{\bC \tp \Category} \left(\bC^{\var{Op}}\right)^{\var{Op}} ≡ \bC
|
||||||
|
@ -713,10 +719,10 @@ Univalence does not follow immediately from univalence for types:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
$$(A ≡ B) ≃ (A ≃ B)$$
|
$$(A ≡ B) ≃ (A ≃ B)$$
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Because here $A, B \tp \Type$ whereas the objects in this category have the type
|
because here $A, B \tp \Type$, whereas the objects in this category
|
||||||
$\Set$ so we cannot form the type $\var{hA} ≃ \var{hB}$ for objects
|
have the type $\Set$ so we cannot form the type $\var{hA} ≃ \var{hB}$
|
||||||
$\var{hA}\;\var{hB} \tp \Set$. In stead I show that this category
|
for objects $\var{hA}\;\var{hB} \tp \Set$. Instead I show that this
|
||||||
satisfies:
|
category satisfies:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
(\var{hA} ≡ \var{hB}) ≃ (\var{hA} ≊ \var{hB})
|
(\var{hA} ≡ \var{hB}) ≃ (\var{hA} ≊ \var{hB})
|
||||||
|
@ -734,7 +740,7 @@ of equivalences:
|
||||||
& ≃ ((A, s_A) ≊ (B, s_B)) && \text{\ref{eq:equivSig} and \ref{eq:equivIso}}
|
& ≃ ((A, s_A) ≊ (B, s_B)) && \text{\ref{eq:equivSig} and \ref{eq:equivIso}}
|
||||||
\end{align*}
|
\end{align*}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
And since $≃$ is an equivalence relation we can chain these equivalences
|
Since $≃$ is an equivalence relation we can chain these equivalences
|
||||||
together. Step one will be proven with the lemma:
|
together. Step one will be proven with the lemma:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
|
@ -753,19 +759,20 @@ for types. Step three will be proven with the following lemma:
|
||||||
∏_{a \tp A} \left( P\ a ≃ Q\ a \right) → ∑_{a \tp A} P\ a ≃ ∑_{a \tp A} Q\ a
|
∏_{a \tp A} \left( P\ a ≃ Q\ a \right) → ∑_{a \tp A} P\ a ≃ ∑_{a \tp A} Q\ a
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Which says that if two type-families are equivalent at all points, then pairs
|
which says that if two type-families are equivalent at all points,
|
||||||
with identical first components and these families as second components will
|
then pairs with identical first components and these families as
|
||||||
also be equivalent. For our purposes $P ≜ \isEquiv\ A\ B$ and $Q ≜
|
second components will also be equivalent. For our purposes $P ≜
|
||||||
\Isomorphism$. So we must finally prove:
|
\isEquiv\ A\ B$ and $Q ≜ \Isomorphism$. We must finally prove:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
\label{eq:equivIso}
|
\label{eq:equivIso}
|
||||||
∏_{f \tp A → B} \left( \isEquiv\ A\ B\ f ≃ \Isomorphism\ f \right)
|
∏_{f \tp A → B} \left( \isEquiv\ A\ B\ f ≃ \Isomorphism\ f \right)
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
First, lets prove \ref{eq:equivPropSig}: Let $propP \tp ∏_{a \tp A} \isProp\ (P\ a)$ and $x\;y \tp ∑_{a \tp A} P\ a$ be given. Because
|
Lets us first prove \ref{eq:equivPropSig}: Let $propP \tp ∏_{a \tp A}
|
||||||
of $\var{fromIsomorphism}$ it suffices to give an isomorphism between
|
\isProp\ (P\ a)$ and $x\;y \tp ∑_{a \tp A} P\ a$ be given. Because of
|
||||||
$x ≡ y$ and $\fst\ x ≡ \fst\ y$:
|
$\var{fromIsomorphism}$ it suffices to give an isomorphism between $x
|
||||||
|
≡ y$ and $\fst\ x ≡ \fst\ y$:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
%% FIXME: Too much alignement?
|
%% FIXME: Too much alignement?
|
||||||
\begin{equation*}
|
\begin{equation*}
|
||||||
|
@ -778,7 +785,7 @@ $x ≡ y$ and $\fst\ x ≡ \fst\ y$:
|
||||||
\end{equation*}
|
\end{equation*}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Here $\var{lemSig}$ is a lemma that says that if the second component
|
Here $\var{lemSig}$ is a lemma that says that if the second component
|
||||||
of a pair is a proposition, it suffices to give a path between its
|
of a pair is a proposition it suffices to give a path between its
|
||||||
first components to construct an equality of the two pairs:
|
first components to construct an equality of the two pairs:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align*}
|
\begin{align*}
|
||||||
|
@ -811,7 +818,7 @@ choose:
|
||||||
\end{align*}
|
\end{align*}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
As mentioned in section \S\ref{sec:equiv}. These maps are not in general inverses
|
As mentioned in section \S\ref{sec:equiv}. These maps are not in general inverses
|
||||||
of each other. In stead, we will use the fact that $A$ and $B$ are sets. The first thing we must prove is:
|
of each other. Instead, we will use the fact that $A$ and $B$ are sets. The first thing we must prove is:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align*}
|
\begin{align*}
|
||||||
\var{fromIso} \comp \var{toIso} ≡ \identity_{\isEquiv\ f}
|
\var{fromIso} \comp \var{toIso} ≡ \identity_{\isEquiv\ f}
|
||||||
|
@ -843,20 +850,22 @@ $\mathcal{X}$ and $\mathcal{Y}$ denotes the witnesses that $x$
|
||||||
& = y
|
& = y
|
||||||
\end{align*}
|
\end{align*}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
For the other (dependent) path we can prove that being-an-inverse-of is a
|
For the other (dependent) path we can prove that being-an-inverse-of
|
||||||
proposition and then use $\lemPropF$. So we prove the generalization:
|
is a proposition and then use $\lemPropF$. To this end we prove the
|
||||||
|
generalization:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
\label{eq:propAreInversesGen}
|
\label{eq:propAreInversesGen}
|
||||||
∏_{g \tp B → A} \isProp\ (\var{AreInverses}\ f\ g)
|
∏_{g \tp B → A} \isProp\ (\var{AreInverses}\ f\ g)
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
But $\var{AreInverses}\ f\ g$ is a pair of equations on arrows, so we use
|
but $\var{AreInverses}\ f\ g$ is a pair of equations on arrows, so we
|
||||||
$\propSig$ and the fact that both $A$ and $B$ are sets to close this proof.
|
use $\propSig$ and the fact that both $A$ and $B$ are sets to close
|
||||||
|
this proof.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
%% \subsection{Category of categories}
|
%% \subsection{Category of categories}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
%% Note that this category does in fact not exist. In stead I provide
|
%% Note that this category does in fact not exist. Instead I provide
|
||||||
%% the definition of the ``raw'' category as well as some of the laws.
|
%% the definition of the ``raw'' category as well as some of the laws.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
%% Furthermore I provide some helpful lemmas about this raw category.
|
%% Furthermore I provide some helpful lemmas about this raw category.
|
||||||
|
@ -878,13 +887,13 @@ $$
|
||||||
∏_{\bC \tp \Category} ∏_{A\;B \tp \Object} \isProp\ (\var{Product}\ \bC\ A\ B)
|
∏_{\bC \tp \Category} ∏_{A\;B \tp \Object} \isProp\ (\var{Product}\ \bC\ A\ B)
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Where $\var{Product}\ \bC\ A\ B$ denotes the type of products of
|
where $\var{Product}\ \bC\ A\ B$ denotes the type of products of
|
||||||
objects $A$ and $B$ in the category $\bC$. I do this by constructing a
|
objects $A$ and $B$ in the category $\bC$. I do this by constructing
|
||||||
category whose terminal objects are equivalent to products in $\bC$,
|
a category whose terminal objects are equivalent to products in $\bC$.
|
||||||
and since terminal objects are propositional in a proper category and
|
Since terminal objects are propositional in a proper category and
|
||||||
equivalences preserve homotopy level, then we know that products are
|
equivalences preserve homotopy level, then we know that products are
|
||||||
also propositions. But before we get to that, we recall the definition
|
also propositions. But before we get to that, we recall the
|
||||||
of products.
|
definition of products.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\subsection{Definition of products}
|
\subsection{Definition of products}
|
||||||
Given a category $\bC$ and two objects $A$ and $B$ in $\bC$ we say
|
Given a category $\bC$ and two objects $A$ and $B$ in $\bC$ we say
|
||||||
|
@ -908,9 +917,9 @@ The arrow $\pi$ is called the product (arrow) of $f$ and $g$.
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\subsection{Span category}
|
\subsection{Span category}
|
||||||
Given a base category $\bC$ and two objects in this category $\pairA$
|
Given a base category $\bC$ and two objects in this category $\pairA$
|
||||||
and $\pairB$ we construct the \nomenindex{span category}. The type of
|
and $\pairB$ we construct the \nomenindex{span category}. The type of
|
||||||
objects in this category shall be an object in the underlying
|
objects in this category shall be an object in the underlying
|
||||||
category, $X$, and two arrows (also from the underlying category)
|
category, $X$ and two arrows (also from the underlying category)
|
||||||
$\Arrow\ X\ \pairA$ and $\Arrow\ X\ \pairB$.
|
$\Arrow\ X\ \pairA$ and $\Arrow\ X\ \pairB$.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\newcommand\pairf{\ensuremath{f}}
|
\newcommand\pairf{\ensuremath{f}}
|
||||||
|
@ -974,30 +983,32 @@ The proof obligations consists of two things. The first one is:
|
||||||
(h \lll g) \lll f
|
(h \lll g) \lll f
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
And the other proof obligation is that the witness to \ref{eq:pairArrowLaw} for
|
The other proof obligation is that the witness to
|
||||||
the left-hand-side and the right-hand-side are the same.
|
\ref{eq:pairArrowLaw} for the left-hand-side and the right-hand-side
|
||||||
|
are the same.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
The proof of the first goal comes directly from the underlying
|
The proof of the first goal comes directly from the underlying
|
||||||
category. The type of the second goal is very complicated. I will not
|
category. The type of the second goal is very complicated. I will
|
||||||
write it out in full here, but for the purpose of the present
|
not write it out in full here, but for the purpose of this exposition
|
||||||
exposition it will suffices to show the type of the path-space. Note
|
it will suffice to show the type of the path space. Note that the
|
||||||
that the arrows in \ref{eq:productAssoc} are arrows between objects on
|
arrows in \ref{eq:productAssoc} are arrows between objects on the form
|
||||||
the form $\wideoverbar{A} = (A , a_{\pairA} , a_{\pairB})$ to
|
$\wideoverbar{A} = (A , a_{\pairA} , a_{\pairB})$ to $\wideoverbar{D}
|
||||||
$\wideoverbar{D} = (D , d_{\pairA} , d_{\pairB})$ where $a_{\pairA}$,
|
= (D , d_{\pairA} , d_{\pairB})$ where $a_{\pairA}$, $a_{\pairB}$,
|
||||||
$a_{\pairB}$, $d_{\pairA}$ and $d_{\pairB}$ are arrows in the
|
$d_{\pairA}$ and $d_{\pairB}$ are arrows in the underlying category.
|
||||||
underlying category. Given that $p$ is the chosen proof of
|
Given that $p$ is the chosen proof of \ref{eq:productAssocUnderlying}
|
||||||
\ref{eq:productAssocUnderlying} we then have that the witness to
|
we then have that the witness to \ref{eq:pairArrowLaw} vary over the
|
||||||
\ref{eq:pairArrowLaw} vary over the type:
|
type:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
\label{eq:productPath}
|
\label{eq:productPath}
|
||||||
λ \; i → d_{\pairA} \lll p\ i ≡ a_{\pairA} × d_{\pairB} \lll p\ i ≡ a_{\pairB}
|
λ \; i → d_{\pairA} \lll p\ i ≡ a_{\pairA} × d_{\pairB} \lll p\ i ≡ a_{\pairB}
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
And these paths are in the type of the hom-set of the underlying category, so
|
These paths are in the type of the hom-set of the underlying
|
||||||
they are mere propositions. We cannot apply the fact that arrows in $\bC$ are
|
category, so they are mere propositions. We cannot apply the fact
|
||||||
sets directly, however, since $\isSet$ only talks about non-dependent paths, in
|
that arrows in $\bC$ are sets directly, however, since $\isSet$ only
|
||||||
stead we generalize \ref{eq:productPath} to:
|
talks about non-dependent paths, instead we generalize
|
||||||
|
\ref{eq:productPath} to:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
\label{eq:productEqPrinc}
|
\label{eq:productEqPrinc}
|
||||||
|
@ -1005,33 +1016,33 @@ stead we generalize \ref{eq:productPath} to:
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
For all objects $X , x_{\pairA} , x_{\pairB}$ and $Y , y_{\pairA} ,
|
For all objects $X , x_{\pairA} , x_{\pairB}$ and $Y , y_{\pairA} ,
|
||||||
y_{\pairB}$, but this follows from the fact that $∏$ and $∑$ preserve
|
y_{\pairB}$. This follows from the fact that $∏$ and $∑$ preserve
|
||||||
homotopical structure. This gives us an equality principle for arrows
|
homotopical structure. \ref{eq:productEqPrinc} gives us an equality
|
||||||
in this category that says that to prove two arrows $f, f_0, f_1$ and
|
principle for arrows in this category. The equality principle says
|
||||||
$g, g_0, g_1$ equal it suffices to give a proof that $f$ and $g$ are
|
that to prove two arrows $(f, f_0, f_1)$ and $(g, g_0, g_1)$ equal it
|
||||||
equal.
|
suffices to give a proof that $f$ and $g$ are equal.
|
||||||
%% %
|
%% %
|
||||||
%% $$
|
%% $$
|
||||||
%% ∏_{(f, f_0, f_1)\; (g,g_0,g_1) \tp \Arrow\ X\ Y} f ≡ g \to (f, f_0, f_1) ≡ (g,g_0,g_1)
|
%% ∏_{(f, f_0, f_1)\; (g,g_0,g_1) \tp \Arrow\ X\ Y} f ≡ g \to (f, f_0, f_1) ≡ (g,g_0,g_1)
|
||||||
%% $$
|
%% $$
|
||||||
%% %
|
%% %
|
||||||
And thus we have proven \ref{eq:productAssoc} simply with
|
And thus we have proven \ref{eq:productAssoc} using
|
||||||
\ref{eq:productAssocUnderlying}.
|
\ref{eq:productAssocUnderlying}.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
Now we must prove that arrows form a set:
|
We must now prove that the arrows form a set:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
\isSet\ (\Arrow\ \wideoverbar{X}\ \wideoverbar{Y})
|
\isSet\ (\Arrow\ \wideoverbar{X}\ \wideoverbar{Y})
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Since pairs preserve homotopical structure this reduces to the two
|
Since pairs preserve homotopical structure this reduces to the
|
||||||
obligations:
|
following two obligations: The first one is:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
\isSet\ (\bC.\Arrow\ X\ Y)
|
\isSet\ (\bC.\Arrow\ X\ Y)
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Which holds. And
|
which holds. The other one is:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
∏_{f \tp \Arrow\ X\ Y}
|
∏_{f \tp \Arrow\ X\ Y}
|
||||||
|
@ -1040,15 +1051,16 @@ $$
|
||||||
\right)
|
\right)
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
This we get from \ref{eq:productEqPrinc} and the fact that homotopical structure
|
We get this from \ref{eq:productEqPrinc} and the fact that homotopical
|
||||||
is cumulative.
|
structure is cumulative.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
This finishes the proof that this is a valid pre-category.
|
That concludes the proof that this is a valid pre-category.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\subsubsection{Univalence}
|
\subsubsection{Univalence}
|
||||||
To prove that this is a proper category it must be shown that it is univalent.
|
To prove that this is a proper category we must additionally prove the
|
||||||
That is, for any two objects $\mathcal{X} = (X, x_{\mathcal{A}} , x_{\mathcal{B}})$
|
univalence criterion. That is, for any two objects $\mathcal{X} = (X,
|
||||||
and $\mathcal{Y} = Y, y_{\mathcal{A}}, y_{\mathcal{B}}$ I will show:
|
x_{\mathcal{A}} , x_{\mathcal{B}})$ and $\mathcal{Y} = Y,
|
||||||
|
y_{\mathcal{A}}, y_{\mathcal{B}}$ I will show:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
(\mathcal{X} ≡ \mathcal{Y}) \cong (\mathcal{X} ≊ \mathcal{Y})
|
(\mathcal{X} ≡ \mathcal{Y}) \cong (\mathcal{X} ≊ \mathcal{Y})
|
||||||
|
@ -1075,8 +1087,8 @@ The next types will be the triple:
|
||||||
%% \end{split}
|
%% \end{split}
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
The next type is very similar, but in stead of a path we will have an
|
The next type is very similar, but instead of a path we will have an
|
||||||
isomorphism, and create a path from this:
|
isomorphism and create a path from this:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
\label{eq:univ-2}
|
\label{eq:univ-2}
|
||||||
|
@ -1087,7 +1099,7 @@ isomorphism, and create a path from this:
|
||||||
\end{split}
|
\end{split}
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Where $\widetilde{p} ≜ \isoToId\ \var{iso} \tp X ≡ Y$.
|
where $\widetilde{p} ≜ \isoToId\ \var{iso} \tp X ≡ Y$.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
Finally we have the type:
|
Finally we have the type:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
|
@ -1096,10 +1108,10 @@ Finally we have the type:
|
||||||
(X , x_{\mathcal{A}} , x_{\mathcal{B}}) ≊ (Y , y_{\mathcal{A}} , y_{\mathcal{B}})
|
(X , x_{\mathcal{A}} , x_{\mathcal{B}}) ≊ (Y , y_{\mathcal{A}} , y_{\mathcal{B}})
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
So the proof is a chain of isomorphisms between the types
|
The proof is a chain of isomorphisms between the types
|
||||||
\ref{eq:univ-0}, \ref{eq:univ-1}, \ref{eq:univ-2} and
|
\ref{eq:univ-0}, \ref{eq:univ-1}, \ref{eq:univ-2} and \ref{eq:univ-3}.
|
||||||
\ref{eq:univ-3}. I will highlight the most interesting bits of this
|
I will highlight the most interesting bits of this proof. For the
|
||||||
proof. For the full proof see the implementation in the module:
|
full proof see the implementation in the same module:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{center}
|
\begin{center}
|
||||||
\sourcelink{Cat.Categories.Span}
|
\sourcelink{Cat.Categories.Span}
|
||||||
|
@ -1116,13 +1128,13 @@ This proof of this has been omitted but can be found in the module:
|
||||||
\sourcelink{Cat.Categories.Span}
|
\sourcelink{Cat.Categories.Span}
|
||||||
\end{center}
|
\end{center}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\emph{Proposition} \ref{eq:univ-2} is isomorphic to \ref{eq:univ-3}: For this I
|
\emph{Proposition} \ref{eq:univ-2} is isomorphic to \ref{eq:univ-3}:
|
||||||
will show two corollaries of \ref{eq:coeCod}: For an isomorphism $(\iota,
|
For this I will show two corollaries of \ref{eq:coeCod}: For an
|
||||||
\inv{\iota}, \var{inv}) \tp A \cong B$, arrows $f \tp \Arrow\ A\ X$, $g \tp
|
isomorphism $(\iota, \inv{\iota}, \var{inv}) \tp A \cong B$, arrows $f
|
||||||
\Arrow\ B\ X$ and a heterogeneous path between them, $q \tp \Path\ (\lambda\; i
|
\tp \Arrow\ A\ X$, $g \tp \Arrow\ B\ X$ and a heterogeneous path
|
||||||
→ p_{\var{dom}}\ i)\ f\ g$, where $p_{\var{dom}} \tp \Arrow\ A\ X ≡
|
between them, $q \tp \Path\ (\lambda\; i → p_{\var{dom}}\ i)\ f\ g$,
|
||||||
\Arrow\ B\ X$ is a path induced by $\var{iso}$, we have the following two
|
where $p_{\var{dom}} \tp \Arrow\ A\ X ≡ \Arrow\ B\ X$ is a path
|
||||||
results
|
induced by $\var{iso}$, we have the following two results
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
\label{eq:domain-twist-0}
|
\label{eq:domain-twist-0}
|
||||||
|
@ -1157,16 +1169,17 @@ shall be:
|
||||||
f \tp \Arrow\ X\ Y
|
f \tp \Arrow\ X\ Y
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
To show that this choice fits the bill I must now verify that it satisfies
|
To show that this choice fits the bill, I must verify that it
|
||||||
\ref{eq:pairArrowLaw}, which in this case becomes:
|
satisfies \ref{eq:pairArrowLaw}, which in this case becomes:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
(y_{\mathcal{A}} \lll f ≡ x_{\mathcal{A}}) × (y_{\mathcal{B}} \lll f ≡ x_{\mathcal{B}})
|
(y_{\mathcal{A}} \lll f ≡ x_{\mathcal{A}}) × (y_{\mathcal{B}} \lll f ≡ x_{\mathcal{B}})
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Which, since $f$ is an isomorphism and $p_{\mathcal{A}}$ (resp.\ $p_{\mathcal{B}}$)
|
which, since $f$ is an isomorphism and $p_{\mathcal{A}}$
|
||||||
is a path varying according to a path constructed from this isomorphism, this is
|
(resp.\ $p_{\mathcal{B}}$) is a path varying according to a path
|
||||||
exactly what \ref{eq:domain-twist-0} gives us.
|
constructed from this isomorphism, this is exactly what
|
||||||
|
\ref{eq:domain-twist-0} gives us.
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
The other direction is quite analogous. We choose $\inv{f}$ as the morphism and
|
The other direction is quite analogous. We choose $\inv{f}$ as the morphism and
|
||||||
prove that it satisfies \ref{eq:pairArrowLaw} with \ref{eq:domain-twist-1}.
|
prove that it satisfies \ref{eq:pairArrowLaw} with \ref{eq:domain-twist-1}.
|
||||||
|
@ -1222,7 +1235,7 @@ This is achieved with the following lemma:
|
||||||
\Path\ (λ \; i → q\ i)\ a\ b
|
\Path\ (λ \; i → q\ i)\ a\ b
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Which is used without proof. See the implementation for the details.
|
which is used without proof. See the implementation for the details.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\ref{eq:product-paths} is then proven with the propositions:
|
\ref{eq:product-paths} is then proven with the propositions:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
|
@ -1249,7 +1262,7 @@ isomorphism-of is a proposition and that arrows (in both categories)
|
||||||
are sets. The reader is referred to the implementation for the full
|
are sets. The reader is referred to the implementation for the full
|
||||||
gory details.
|
gory details.
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\subsection{Products are propositions}
|
\subsection{To have products is a property of a category}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Now that we have constructed the span category\index{span category} I
|
Now that we have constructed the span category\index{span category} I
|
||||||
will demonstrate how to use this to prove that products are
|
will demonstrate how to use this to prove that products are
|
||||||
|
@ -1264,14 +1277,19 @@ that terminal objects in the span category are equivalent to products:
|
||||||
\var{Terminal} ≃ \var{Product}\ ℂ\ \mathcal{A}\ \mathcal{B}
|
\var{Terminal} ≃ \var{Product}\ ℂ\ \mathcal{A}\ \mathcal{B}
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
And as always we do this by constructing an isomorphism:
|
and as always we do this by constructing an isomorphism:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
In the direction $\var{Terminal} → \var{Product}\ ℂ\ \mathcal{A}\ \mathcal{B}$
|
In the direction
|
||||||
we are given a terminal object $X, x_𝒜, x_ℬ$. $X$ will be the product-object and
|
%
|
||||||
$x_𝒜, x_ℬ$ will be the product arrows, so it just remains to verify that this is
|
$$
|
||||||
indeed a product. That is, for an object $Y$ and two arrows $y_𝒜 \tp
|
\var{Terminal} → \var{Product}\ ℂ\ \mathcal{A}\ \mathcal{B}
|
||||||
\Arrow\ Y\ 𝒜$, $y_ℬ\ \Arrow\ Y\ ℬ$ we must find a unique arrow $f \tp
|
$$
|
||||||
\Arrow\ Y\ X$ satisfying:
|
%
|
||||||
|
we are given a terminal object $X, x_𝒜, x_ℬ$. $X$ will be the
|
||||||
|
product-object and $x_𝒜, x_ℬ$ will be the product arrows, so it just
|
||||||
|
remains to verify that this is indeed a product. That is, for an
|
||||||
|
object $Y$ and two arrows $y_𝒜 \tp \Arrow\ Y\ 𝒜$, $y_ℬ\ \Arrow\ Y\ ℬ$
|
||||||
|
we must find a unique arrow $f \tp \Arrow\ Y\ X$ satisfying:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
\label{eq:pairCondRev}
|
\label{eq:pairCondRev}
|
||||||
|
@ -1282,23 +1300,23 @@ indeed a product. That is, for an object $Y$ and two arrows $y_𝒜 \tp
|
||||||
%% \end{split}
|
%% \end{split}
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Since $X, x_𝒜, x_ℬ$ is a terminal object there is a \emph{unique}
|
Since $X, x_𝒜, x_ℬ$ is a terminal object, there is a \emph{unique}
|
||||||
arrow from this object to any other object, so in particular also $Y,
|
arrow from this object to any other object. In particular we have $Y,
|
||||||
y_𝒜, y_ℬ$. The arrow we will play the role of $f$ and it immediately
|
y_𝒜, y_ℬ$. The arrow we will play the role of $f$ and it immediately
|
||||||
satisfies \ref{eq:pairCondRev}. Any other arrow satisfying these
|
satisfies \ref{eq:pairCondRev}. Any other arrow satisfying these
|
||||||
conditions will be equal since $f$ is unique.
|
conditions will be equal since $f$ is unique.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
For the other direction we are now given a product $X, x_𝒜, x_ℬ$.
|
For the other direction we are now given a product $X, x_𝒜, x_ℬ$.
|
||||||
Again this will be the terminal object. So now it remains that for
|
Again this will be the terminal object. Now it remains that for any
|
||||||
any other object there is a unique arrow from that object into $X,
|
other object there is a unique arrow from that object into $X, x_𝒜,
|
||||||
x_𝒜, x_ℬ$. Let $Y, y_𝒜, y_ℬ$ be another object. As the arrow
|
x_ℬ$. Let $Y, y_𝒜, y_ℬ$ be another object. As the arrow
|
||||||
$\Arrow\ Y\ X$ we choose the product-arrow $y_𝒜 \x y_ℬ$. Since this
|
$\Arrow\ Y\ X$ we choose the product-arrow $y_𝒜 \x y_ℬ$. Since this
|
||||||
is a product-arrow it satisfies \ref{eq:pairCondRev}. Let us name the
|
is a product-arrow it satisfies \ref{eq:pairCondRev}. Let us name the
|
||||||
witness to this $\phi_{y_𝒜 \x y_ℬ}$. So we have picked as our center
|
witness to this $\phi_{y_𝒜 \x y_ℬ}$. We have picked as our center of
|
||||||
of contraction $y_𝒜 \x y_ℬ , \phi_{y_𝒜 \x y_ℬ}$ we must now show that
|
contraction $y_𝒜 \x y_ℬ , \phi_{y_𝒜 \x y_ℬ}$ we must now show that it
|
||||||
it is contractible. So let $f \tp \Arrow\ X\ Y$ and $\phi_f$ be given
|
is contractible. Let $f \tp \Arrow\ X\ Y$ and $\phi_f$ be given (here
|
||||||
(here $\phi_f$ is the proof that $f$ satisfies \ref{eq:pairCondRev}).
|
$\phi_f$ is the proof that $f$ satisfies \ref{eq:pairCondRev}). The
|
||||||
The proof will be a pair of proofs:
|
proof will be a pair of proofs:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{alignat}{3}
|
\begin{alignat}{3}
|
||||||
p \tp & \Path\ (\lambda\; i → \Arrow\ X\ Y)\quad
|
p \tp & \Path\ (\lambda\; i → \Arrow\ X\ Y)\quad
|
||||||
|
@ -1330,11 +1348,10 @@ $$
|
||||||
Which follows from arrows being sets and pairs preserving such. Thus we can
|
Which follows from arrows being sets and pairs preserving such. Thus we can
|
||||||
close the final proof with an application of $\lemPropF$.
|
close the final proof with an application of $\lemPropF$.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
This concludes the proof
|
This concludes the proof $\var{Terminal} ≃
|
||||||
$\var{Terminal} ≃ \var{Product}\ ℂ\ \mathcal{A}\ \mathcal{B}$
|
\var{Product}\ ℂ\ \mathcal{A}\ \mathcal{B}$ and since we have that
|
||||||
and since we have that equivalences preserve homotopic levels along
|
equivalences preserve homotopic levels along with \ref{eq:termProp} we
|
||||||
with \ref{eq:termProp} we get our final result. That is, in any
|
get our final result. That is, in any category $\bC$ we have:
|
||||||
category $\bC$ we have:
|
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
∏_{A, B \tp \Object} \isProp\ (\var{Product}\ \bC\ A\ B)
|
∏_{A, B \tp \Object} \isProp\ (\var{Product}\ \bC\ A\ B)
|
||||||
|
@ -1354,7 +1371,7 @@ following data:
|
||||||
\fmap & \tp ℂ.\Arrow\ A\ B → 𝔻.\Arrow\ (\omapF\ A)\ (\omapF\ B)
|
\fmap & \tp ℂ.\Arrow\ A\ B → 𝔻.\Arrow\ (\omapF\ A)\ (\omapF\ B)
|
||||||
\end{align*}
|
\end{align*}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
And the following laws:
|
and the following laws:
|
||||||
\begin{align*}
|
\begin{align*}
|
||||||
\fmap\ ℂ.\identity & ≡ 𝔻.identity \\
|
\fmap\ ℂ.\identity & ≡ 𝔻.identity \\
|
||||||
\fmap\ (g \clll f) & ≡ \fmap\ g \dlll \fmap\ f
|
\fmap\ (g \clll f) & ≡ \fmap\ g \dlll \fmap\ f
|
||||||
|
@ -1462,7 +1479,7 @@ The objects $X$ and $Y$ are implicitly universally quantified. With this data w
|
||||||
f \fish g & ≜ f \rrr (\bind\ g)
|
f \fish g & ≜ f \rrr (\bind\ g)
|
||||||
\end{align*}
|
\end{align*}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
It is interesting to note here that this formulation does mention
|
It is interesting to note here that this formulation does not mention
|
||||||
functors nor natural transformations. All we have here is a regular
|
functors nor natural transformations. All we have here is a regular
|
||||||
map on objects and a pair of arrows.
|
map on objects and a pair of arrows.
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
|
@ -1502,7 +1519,7 @@ In the monoidal formulation we can define $\bind$:
|
||||||
\bind\ f ≜ \join \lll \fmap\ f
|
\bind\ f ≜ \join \lll \fmap\ f
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
And likewise in the Kleisli formulation we can define $\join$:
|
and likewise in the Kleisli formulation we can define $\join$:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
\join ≜ \bind\ \identity
|
\join ≜ \bind\ \identity
|
||||||
|
@ -1596,7 +1613,7 @@ the monoidal formulation we pick:
|
||||||
We must now not only show the monad laws given for the monoidal
|
We must now not only show the monad laws given for the monoidal
|
||||||
formulation (\monoidallaws), we must also verify that $\EndoR$ is a
|
formulation (\monoidallaws), we must also verify that $\EndoR$ is a
|
||||||
functor and that $\pure$ and $\join$ are natural transformations. I
|
functor and that $\pure$ and $\join$ are natural transformations. I
|
||||||
will ommit this here. In stead we shall see how these two mappings
|
will ommit this here. Instead we shall see how these two mappings
|
||||||
are indeed inverses. The full construction can be found in the
|
are indeed inverses. The full construction can be found in the
|
||||||
module:
|
module:
|
||||||
\begin{center}
|
\begin{center}
|
||||||
|
@ -1614,7 +1631,7 @@ other. To recap, these maps are:
|
||||||
→ (\EndoR, \pure, \bind\ \identity)
|
→ (\EndoR, \pure, \bind\ \identity)
|
||||||
\end{align*}
|
\end{align*}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Where $\EndoR ≜ (\omapR, \bind\ (\pure \lll f))$. The proof that
|
where $\EndoR ≜ (\omapR, \bind\ (\pure \lll f))$. The proof that
|
||||||
this is indeed a functor is left implicit as well as the monad laws.
|
this is indeed a functor is left implicit as well as the monad laws.
|
||||||
Likewise the proof that $\pure$ and $\bind\ \identity$ are natural
|
Likewise the proof that $\pure$ and $\bind\ \identity$ are natural
|
||||||
transformations are left implicit. The inverse map will be:
|
transformations are left implicit. The inverse map will be:
|
||||||
|
@ -1639,9 +1656,9 @@ For \ref{eq:monad-forwards} let $(\omapR, \pure, \bind)$ be a monad in
|
||||||
the Kleisli form. Since being-a-monad is a proposition\footnote{The
|
the Kleisli form. Since being-a-monad is a proposition\footnote{The
|
||||||
proof was omitted here but can be found in the implementation.} we
|
proof was omitted here but can be found in the implementation.} we
|
||||||
get an equality-principle for kleisli-monads that say that to equate
|
get an equality-principle for kleisli-monads that say that to equate
|
||||||
two such monads it suffices to equate their data-part. So it suffices
|
two such monads it suffices to equate their data part. It thus
|
||||||
to equate the data-parts of the \ref{eq:monad-forwards}. Such a proof
|
suffices to equate the data parts of \ref{eq:monad-forwards}. Such a
|
||||||
is a triple equating the three projections of
|
proof is a triple equating the three projections of
|
||||||
\ref{eq:monad-kleisli-data}. The first two hold definitionally --
|
\ref{eq:monad-kleisli-data}. The first two hold definitionally --
|
||||||
essentially one just wraps and unwraps the morphism in a functor. For
|
essentially one just wraps and unwraps the morphism in a functor. For
|
||||||
the last equation a little more work is required:
|
the last equation a little more work is required:
|
||||||
|
|
|
@ -1,17 +1,17 @@
|
||||||
\chapter{Introduction}
|
\chapter{Introduction}
|
||||||
This thesis is a case-study in the application of cubical Agda in the
|
This thesis is a case study in the application of cubical Agda to the
|
||||||
context of category theory. At the center of this is the notion of
|
formalization of category theory. At the center of this is the notion
|
||||||
\nomenindex{equality}. In type-theory there are two pervasive notions
|
of \nomenindex{equality}. There are two pervasive notions of equality
|
||||||
of equality: \nomenindex{judgmental equality} and
|
in type theory: \nomenindex{judgmental equality} and
|
||||||
\nomenindex{propositional equality}. Judgmental equality is a property
|
\nomenindex{propositional equality}. Judgmental equality is a property
|
||||||
of the type system. Judgmental equality on the other hand is usually
|
of the type system. Propositional equality on the other hand is
|
||||||
defined \emph{within} the system. When introducing definitions this
|
usually defined \emph{within} the system. When introducing
|
||||||
report will use the symbol $\defeq$. Judgmental equalities will be
|
definitions this report will use the symbol $\defeq$. Judgmental
|
||||||
denoted with $=$ and for propositional equalities the notation
|
equalities will be denoted with $=$ and for propositional equalities
|
||||||
$\equiv$ is used.
|
the notation $\equiv$ is used.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
The rules of judgmental equality are related with $β$- and
|
The rules of judgmental equality are related with $β$- and
|
||||||
$η$-reduction which gives a notion of computation in a given type
|
$η$-reduction, which gives a notion of computation in a given type
|
||||||
theory.
|
theory.
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
There are some properties that one usually want judgmental equality to
|
There are some properties that one usually want judgmental equality to
|
||||||
|
@ -19,20 +19,21 @@ satisfy. It must be \nomenindex{sound}, enjoy \nomenindex{canonicity}
|
||||||
and be a \nomenindex{congruence relation}. Soundness means that things
|
and be a \nomenindex{congruence relation}. Soundness means that things
|
||||||
judged to be equal are equal with respects to the \nomenindex{model}
|
judged to be equal are equal with respects to the \nomenindex{model}
|
||||||
of the theory or the \emph{meta theory}. It must be a congruence
|
of the theory or the \emph{meta theory}. It must be a congruence
|
||||||
relation because otherwise the relation certainly does not adhere to
|
relation, because otherwise the relation certainly does not adhere to
|
||||||
our notion of equality. One would be able to conclude things like: $x
|
our notion of equality. E.g.\ One would be able to conclude things
|
||||||
\equiv y \rightarrow f\ x \nequiv f\ y$. Canonicity means that any
|
like: $x \equiv y \rightarrow f\ x \nequiv f\ y$. Canonicity means
|
||||||
well typed term evaluates to a \emph{canonical} form. For example for
|
that any well typed term evaluates to a \emph{canonical} form. For
|
||||||
a closed term $e \tp \bN$ it will be the case that $e$ reduces to $n$
|
example, for a closed term $e \tp \bN$, it will be the case that $e$
|
||||||
applications of $\mathit{suc}$ to $0$ for some $n$; $e =
|
reduces to $n$ applications of $\mathit{suc}$ to $0$ for some $n$;
|
||||||
\mathit{suc}^n\ 0$. Without canonicity terms in the language can get
|
i.e.\ $e = \mathit{suc}^n\ 0$. Without canonicity terms in the
|
||||||
``stuck'' meaning that they do not reduce to a canonical form.
|
language can get ``stuck'', meaning that they do not reduce to a
|
||||||
|
canonical form.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
To work as a programming languages it is necessary for judgmental
|
For a system to work as a programming languages it is necessary for
|
||||||
equality to be \nomenindex{decidable}. Being decidable simply means
|
judgmental equality to be \nomenindex{decidable}. Being decidable
|
||||||
that that an algorithm exists to decide whether two terms are equal.
|
simply means that that an algorithm exists to decide whether two terms
|
||||||
For any practical implementation the decidability must also be
|
are equal. For any practical implementation, the decidability must
|
||||||
effectively computable.
|
also be effectively computable.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
For propositional equality the decidability requirement is relaxed. It
|
For propositional equality the decidability requirement is relaxed. It
|
||||||
is not in general possible to decide the correctness of logical
|
is not in general possible to decide the correctness of logical
|
||||||
|
@ -47,28 +48,27 @@ inhabitant. In extensional type theory the principle of reflection
|
||||||
$$a ≡ b → a = b$$
|
$$a ≡ b → a = b$$
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
is enough to make type checking undecidable. This report focuses on
|
is enough to make type checking undecidable. This report focuses on
|
||||||
Agda which at a glance can be thought of as a version of intensional
|
Agda, which at a glance can be thought of as a version of intensional
|
||||||
type theory. Pattern-matching in regular Agda lets one prove
|
type theory. Pattern-matching in regular Agda lets one prove
|
||||||
\nomenindex{Uniqueness of Identity Proofs} (UIP). UIP states that any
|
\nomenindex{Uniqueness of Identity Proofs} (UIP). UIP states that any
|
||||||
two identity proofs are propositionally identical.
|
two identity proofs are propositionally identical.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
The usual notion of propositional equality in ITT is quite
|
The usual notion of propositional equality in ITT is quite
|
||||||
restrictive. In the next section a few motivating examples will
|
restrictive. In the next section a few motivating examples will be
|
||||||
highlight this. There exist techniques to circumvent these problems,
|
presented that highlight. There exist techniques to circumvent these
|
||||||
as we shall see. This thesis will explore an extension to Agda that
|
problems, as we shall see. This thesis will explore an extension to
|
||||||
redefines the notion of propositional equality and as such is an
|
Agda that redefines the notion of propositional equality and as such
|
||||||
alternative to these other techniques. The extension is called cubical
|
is an alternative to these other techniques. The extension is called
|
||||||
Agda. Cubical Agda drops UIP as this does not permit
|
cubical Agda. Cubical Agda drops UIP, as it does not permit
|
||||||
\nomenindex{functional extensionality} and
|
\nomenindex{functional extensionality} nor \nomenindex{univalence}.
|
||||||
\nomenindex{univalence}. What makes this extension particularly
|
What makes cubical Agda particularly interesting is that it gives a
|
||||||
interesting is that it gives a \emph{constructive} interpretation of
|
\emph{constructive} interpretation of univalence. What all this means
|
||||||
univalence. What all this means will be elaborated in the following
|
will be elaborated in the following sections.
|
||||||
sections.
|
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\section{Motivating examples}
|
\section{Motivating examples}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
In the following two sections I present two examples that illustrate
|
In the following two sections I present two examples that illustrate
|
||||||
some limitations inherent in ITT and -- by extension -- Agda.
|
some limitations inherent in ITT and, by extension, Agda.
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\subsection{Functional extensionality}
|
\subsection{Functional extensionality}
|
||||||
\label{sec:functional-extensionality}%
|
\label{sec:functional-extensionality}%
|
||||||
|
@ -80,9 +80,9 @@ Consider the functions:
|
||||||
\end{align*}%
|
\end{align*}%
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
The term $n + 0$ is \nomenindex{definitionally} equal to $n$, which we
|
The term $n + 0$ is \nomenindex{definitionally} equal to $n$, which we
|
||||||
write as $n + 0 = n$. This is also called \nomenindex{judgmental
|
write as $n + 0 = n$. This is also called \nomenindex{judgmental
|
||||||
equality}. We call it definitional equality because the
|
equality}. We call it definitional equality because the
|
||||||
\emph{equality} arises from the \emph{definition} of $+$ which is:
|
\emph{equality} arises from the \emph{definition} of $+$, which is:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align*}
|
\begin{align*}
|
||||||
+ & \tp \bN \to \bN \to \bN \\
|
+ & \tp \bN \to \bN \to \bN \\
|
||||||
|
@ -90,12 +90,12 @@ write as $n + 0 = n$. This is also called \nomenindex{judgmental
|
||||||
n + (\suc{m}) & \defeq \suc{(n + m)}
|
n + (\suc{m}) & \defeq \suc{(n + m)}
|
||||||
\end{align*}
|
\end{align*}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Note that $0 + n$ is \emph{not} definitionally equal to $n$. This is
|
Note that $0 + n$ is \emph{not} definitionally equal to $n$. This is
|
||||||
because $0 + n$ is in normal form. I.e.\ there is no rule for $+$
|
because $0 + n$ is in normal form. I.e.\ there is no rule for $+$
|
||||||
whose left hand side matches this expression. We do however have that
|
whose left hand side matches this expression. We do, however, have that
|
||||||
they are \nomen{propositionally}{propositional equality} equal, which
|
they are \nomen{propositionally}{propositional equality} equal, which
|
||||||
we write as $n \equiv n + 0$. Propositional equality means that there
|
we write as $n \equiv n + 0$. Propositional equality means that there
|
||||||
is a proof that exhibits this relation. We can do induction over $n$
|
is a proof that exhibits this relation. We can do induction over $n$
|
||||||
to prove this:
|
to prove this:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
|
@ -107,39 +107,38 @@ to prove this:
|
||||||
\end{split}
|
\end{split}
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
This show that zero is a right neutral element hence the name $\var{zrn}$.
|
This show that zero is a right neutral element (hence the name
|
||||||
Since equality is a transitive relation we have that $\forall n \to
|
$\var{zrn}$). Since equality is a transitive relation we have that
|
||||||
\var{zeroLeft}\ n \equiv \var{zeroRight}\ n$. Unfortunately we don't
|
$\forall n \to \var{zeroLeft}\ n \equiv \var{zeroRight}\ n$.
|
||||||
have $\var{zeroLeft} \equiv \var{zeroRight}$. There is no way to
|
Unfortunately we don't have $\var{zeroLeft} \equiv \var{zeroRight}$.
|
||||||
construct a proof asserting the obvious equivalence of
|
There is no way to construct a proof asserting the obvious equivalence
|
||||||
$\var{zeroLeft}$ and $\var{zeroRight}$. Actually showing this is
|
of $\var{zeroLeft}$ and $\var{zeroRight}$. Actually showing this is
|
||||||
outside the scope of this text. Essentially it would involve giving a
|
outside the scope of this text. It would essentially involve giving a
|
||||||
model for our type theory that validates all our axioms but where
|
model for our type theory that validates all our axioms but where
|
||||||
$\var{zeroLeft} \equiv \var{zeroRight}$ is not true. We cannot show
|
$\var{zeroLeft} \equiv \var{zeroRight}$ is not true. We cannot show
|
||||||
that they are equal even though we can prove them equal for all
|
that they are equal even though we can prove them equal for all
|
||||||
points. For functions this is exactly the notion of equality that we
|
points. This is exactly the notion of equality that we are interested
|
||||||
are interested in: Functions are considered equal when they are equal
|
in for functions: Functions are considered equal when they are equal
|
||||||
for all inputs. This is called \nomenindex{pointwise equality}, where
|
for all inputs. This is called \nomenindex{pointwise equality} where
|
||||||
the \emph{points} of a function refer to its arguments.
|
\emph{points} of a function refer to its arguments.
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\subsection{Equality of isomorphic types}
|
\subsection{Equality of isomorphic types}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Let $\top$ denote the unit type -- a type with a single constructor.
|
Let $\top$ denote the unit type -- a type with a single constructor.
|
||||||
In the propositions as types interpretation of type theory $\top$ is
|
In the propositions as types interpretation of type theory $\top$ is
|
||||||
the proposition that is always true. The type $A \x \top$ and $A$ has
|
the proposition that is always true. The type $A \x \top$ and $A$ has
|
||||||
an element for each $a \tp A$. So in a sense they have the same shape
|
an element for each $a \tp A$. So in a sense they have the same shape
|
||||||
(Greek;
|
(Greek; \nomenindex{isomorphic}). The second element of the pair does
|
||||||
\nomenindex{isomorphic}). The second element of the pair does not
|
not add any ``interesting information''. It can be useful to identify
|
||||||
add any ``interesting information''. It can be useful to identify such
|
such types. In fact it is quite commonplace in mathematics. Say we
|
||||||
types. In fact, it is quite commonplace in mathematics. Say we look at
|
look at a set $\{x \mid \phi\ x \land \psi\ x\}$ and somehow conclude
|
||||||
a set $\{x \mid \phi\ x \land \psi\ x\}$ and somehow conclude that
|
that $\psi\ x \equiv \top$ for all $x$. A mathematician would
|
||||||
$\psi\ x \equiv \top$ for all $x$. A mathematician would immediately
|
immediately conclude $\{x \mid \phi\ x \land \psi\ x\} \equiv \{x \mid
|
||||||
conclude $\{x \mid \phi\ x \land \psi\ x\} \equiv \{x \mid \phi\ x\}$
|
\phi\ x\}$ without thinking twice. Unfortunately such an
|
||||||
without thinking twice. Unfortunately such an identification can not
|
identification can not be performed in ITT.
|
||||||
be performed in ITT.
|
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
More specifically what we are interested in is a way of identifying
|
More specifically what we are interested in is a way of identifying
|
||||||
\nomenindex{equivalent} types. I will return to the definition of
|
\nomenindex{equivalent} types. I will return to the definition of
|
||||||
equivalence later in section \S\ref{sec:equiv}, but for now it is
|
equivalence later in section \S\ref{sec:equiv}, but for now it is
|
||||||
sufficient to think of an equivalence as a one-to-one correspondence.
|
sufficient to think of an equivalence as a one-to-one correspondence.
|
||||||
We write $A \simeq B$ to assert that $A$ and $B$ are equivalent types.
|
We write $A \simeq B$ to assert that $A$ and $B$ are equivalent types.
|
||||||
|
@ -155,23 +154,23 @@ and vice versa.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\section{Formalizing Category Theory}
|
\section{Formalizing Category Theory}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
The above examples serve to illustrate a limitation of ITT. One case
|
The above examples serve to illustrate a limitation of ITT. One case
|
||||||
where these limitations are particularly prohibitive is in the study
|
where these limitations are particularly prohibitive is in the study
|
||||||
of Category Theory. At a glance category theory can be described as
|
of Category Theory. At a glance category theory can be described as
|
||||||
``the mathematical study of (abstract) algebras of functions''
|
``the mathematical study of (abstract) algebras of functions''
|
||||||
(\cite{awodey-2006}). By that token functional extensionality is
|
(\cite{awodey-2006}). By that token functional extensionality is
|
||||||
particularly useful for formulating Category Theory. In Category
|
particularly useful for formulating Category Theory. In Category
|
||||||
theory it is also commonplace to identify isomorphic structures and
|
theory it is also commonplace to identify isomorphic structures.
|
||||||
univalence gives us a way to make this notion precise. In fact we can
|
Univalence gives us a way to make this notion precise. In fact we can
|
||||||
formulate this requirement within our formulation of categories by
|
formulate this requirement within our formulation of categories by
|
||||||
requiring the \emph{categories} themselves to be univalent as we shall
|
requiring the \emph{categories} themselves to be univalent as we shall
|
||||||
see in \S\ref{sec:univalence}.
|
see in section \S\ref{sec:univalence}.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\section{Context}
|
\section{Context}
|
||||||
\label{sec:context}
|
\label{sec:context}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
The idea of formalizing Category Theory in proof assistants is not new. There
|
The idea of formalizing Category Theory in proof assistants is not new. There
|
||||||
are a multitude of these available online. Notably:
|
are a multitude of these available online. Notably:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{itemize}
|
\begin{itemize}
|
||||||
\item
|
\item
|
||||||
|
@ -186,20 +185,21 @@ are a multitude of these available online. Notably:
|
||||||
\url{https://github.com/HoTT/HoTT/tree/master/theories/Categories}
|
\url{https://github.com/HoTT/HoTT/tree/master/theories/Categories}
|
||||||
\item
|
\item
|
||||||
A formalization in \emph{CubicalTT} -- a language designed for
|
A formalization in \emph{CubicalTT} -- a language designed for
|
||||||
cubical type theory. Formalizes many different things, but only a
|
cubical type theory. Formalizes many different things, but only a
|
||||||
few concepts from category theory:
|
few concepts from category theory:
|
||||||
\url{https://github.com/mortberg/cubicaltt}
|
\url{https://github.com/mortberg/cubicaltt}
|
||||||
\end{itemize}
|
\end{itemize}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
The contribution of this thesis is to explore how working in a cubical setting
|
The contribution of this thesis is to explore how working in a cubical
|
||||||
will make it possible to prove more things and to reuse proofs and to try and
|
setting will make it possible to prove more things, to reuse proofs
|
||||||
compare some aspects of this formalization with the existing ones.
|
and to compare some aspects of this formalization with the existing
|
||||||
|
ones.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
There are alternative approaches to working in a cubical setting where
|
There are alternative approaches to working in a cubical setting where
|
||||||
one can still have univalence and functional extensionality. One
|
one can still have univalence and functional extensionality. One
|
||||||
option is to postulate these as axioms. This approach, however, has
|
option is to postulate these as axioms. This approach, however, has
|
||||||
other shortcomings, e.g. you lose \nomenindex{canonicity}
|
other shortcomings, e.g.\ you lose \nomenindex{canonicity}
|
||||||
(\cite[p. 3]{huber-2016}).
|
(\cite[p.\ 3]{huber-2016}).
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
Another approach is to use the \emph{setoid interpretation} of type
|
Another approach is to use the \emph{setoid interpretation} of type
|
||||||
theory (\cite{hofmann-1995,huber-2016}). With this approach one works
|
theory (\cite{hofmann-1995,huber-2016}). With this approach one works
|
||||||
|
@ -207,13 +207,13 @@ with \nomenindex{extensional sets} $(X, \sim)$. That is a type $X \tp
|
||||||
\MCU$ and an equivalence relation $\sim\ \tp X \to X \to \MCU$ on that
|
\MCU$ and an equivalence relation $\sim\ \tp X \to X \to \MCU$ on that
|
||||||
type. Under the setoid interpretation the equivalence relation serve
|
type. Under the setoid interpretation the equivalence relation serve
|
||||||
as a sort of ``local'' propositional equality. Since the developer
|
as a sort of ``local'' propositional equality. Since the developer
|
||||||
gets to pick this relation it is not a~priori a congruence
|
gets to pick this relation, it is not a~priori a congruence
|
||||||
relation. So this must be verified manually by the developer.
|
relation. It must be manually verified by the developer. Furthermore,
|
||||||
Furthermore, functions between different setoids must be shown to be
|
functions between different setoids must be shown to be setoid
|
||||||
setoid homomorphism, that is; they preserve the relation.
|
homomorphism, that is; they preserve the relation.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
This approach has other drawbacks; it does not satisfy all
|
This approach has other drawbacks: It does not satisfy all
|
||||||
propositional equalities of type theory a\~priori. That is, the
|
propositional equalities of type theory a~priori. That is, the
|
||||||
developer must manually show that e.g.\ the relation is a congruence.
|
developer must manually show that e.g.\ the relation is a congruence.
|
||||||
Equational proofs $a \sim_{X} b$ are in some sense `local' to the
|
Equational proofs $a \sim_{X} b$ are in some sense `local' to the
|
||||||
extensional set $(X , \sim)$. To e.g.\ prove that $x ∼ y → f\ x ∼
|
extensional set $(X , \sim)$. To e.g.\ prove that $x ∼ y → f\ x ∼
|
||||||
|
@ -223,23 +223,19 @@ makes it very cumbersome to work with in practice (\cite[p.
|
||||||
4]{huber-2016}).
|
4]{huber-2016}).
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\section{Conventions}
|
\section{Conventions}
|
||||||
In the remainder of this paper I will use the term \nomenindex{Type}
|
In the remainder of this thesis I will use the term \nomenindex{Type}
|
||||||
to describe -- well -- types. Thereby departing from the notation in
|
to describe -- well -- types; thereby departing from the notation in
|
||||||
Agda where the keyword \texttt{Set} refers to types. \nomenindex{Set}
|
Agda where the keyword \texttt{Set} refers to types.
|
||||||
on the other hand shall refer to the homotopical notion of a set. I
|
\nomenindex{Set}, on the other hand, shall refer to the homotopical
|
||||||
will also leave all universe levels implicit. This of course does not
|
notion of a set. I will also leave all universe levels implicit. This
|
||||||
mean that a statement such as $\MCU \tp \MCU$ means that we have
|
of course does not mean that a statement such as $\MCU \tp \MCU$ means
|
||||||
type-in-type but rather that the arguments to the universes are
|
that we have type-in-type but rather that the arguments to the
|
||||||
implicit.
|
universes are implicit.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
And I use the term
|
I use the term \nomenindex{arrow} to refer to morphisms in a category,
|
||||||
\nomenindex{arrow} to refer to morphisms in a category,
|
whereas the terms \nomenindex{morphism}, \nomenindex{map} or
|
||||||
whereas the terms
|
\nomenindex{function} shall be reserved for talking about type
|
||||||
\nomenindex{morphism},
|
theoretic functions; i.e.\ functions in Agda.
|
||||||
\nomenindex{map} or
|
|
||||||
\nomenindex{function}
|
|
||||||
shall be reserved for talking about type theoretic functions; i.e.
|
|
||||||
functions in Agda.
|
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
As already noted $\defeq$ will be used for introducing definitions $=$
|
As already noted $\defeq$ will be used for introducing definitions $=$
|
||||||
will be used to for judgmental equality and $\equiv$ will be used for
|
will be used to for judgmental equality and $\equiv$ will be used for
|
||||||
|
|
Loading…
Reference in a new issue