Remove some TODO-notes, add section on motifs

This commit is contained in:
Frederik Hanghøj Iversen 2018-05-23 18:28:27 +02:00
parent fc7e504359
commit 2d0dfab12a
5 changed files with 114 additions and 70 deletions

View file

@ -1,22 +1,24 @@
\chapter{Conclusion}
This thesis highlighted some issues with the standard inductive definition of
propositional equality used in Agda. Functional extensionality and univalence
are examples of two propositions not admissible in Intensional Type Theory
(ITT). This has a big impact on what is provable and the reusability of proofs.
This issue is overcome with an extension to Agda's type system called Cubical
Agda. With Cubical Agda both functional extensionality and univalence are
admissible. Cubical Agda is more expressive, but there are certain issues that
arise that are not present in standard Agda. For one thing ITT and standard Agda
enjoys Uniqueness of Identity Proofs (UIP). This is not the case in Cubical
Agda. In stead there exists a hierarchy of types with increasing
\nomen{homotopical structure}{homotopy levels}. It turns out to be useful to built the
formalization with this hierarchy in mind as it can simplify proofs
considerably. Another issue one must overcome in Cubical Agda is when a type has
a field whose type depends on a previous field. In this case paths between such
types will be heterogeneous paths. This problem is related to Cubical Agda not
having the K-rule \TODO{Not mentioned anywhere in the report}. In practice it
turns out to be considerably more difficult to work heterogeneous paths than
with homogeneous paths. The thesis demonstrated some techniques to overcome
This thesis highlighted some issues with the standard inductive
definition of propositional equality used in Agda. Functional
extensionality and univalence are examples of two propositions not
admissible in Intensional Type Theory (ITT). This has a big impact on
what is provable and the reusability of proofs. This issue is overcome
with an extension to Agda's type system called Cubical Agda. With
Cubical Agda both functional extensionality and univalence are
admissible. Cubical Agda is more expressive, but there are certain
issues that arise that are not present in standard Agda. For one thing
ITT and standard Agda enjoys Uniqueness of Identity Proofs (UIP). This
is not the case in Cubical Agda. In stead there exists a hierarchy of
types with increasing \nomen{homotopical structure}{homotopy levels}.
It turns out to be useful to built the formalization with this
hierarchy in mind as it can simplify proofs considerably. Another
issue one must overcome in Cubical Agda is when a type has a field
whose type depends on a previous field. In this case paths between
such types will be heterogeneous paths. This problem is related to
Cubical Agda not having the K-rule. In practice it turns out to be
considerably more difficult to work heterogeneous paths than with
homogeneous paths. The thesis demonstrated some techniques to overcome
these difficulties, such as based path-induction.
This thesis formalized some of the core concepts from category theory including;

View file

@ -54,17 +54,18 @@ Judgmental equality in Cubical Agda is encapsulated with the type:
\Path \tp (P \tp I → \MCU) → P\ 0 → P\ 1 → \MCU
\end{equation}
%
$I$ is a special data type (\TODO{that also has special computational properties
AFAIK}) called the index set. $I$ can be thought of simply as the interval on
the real numbers from $0$ to $1$. $P$ is a family of types over the index set
$I$. I will sometimes refer to $P$ as the \nomenindex{path space} of some path $p \tp
\Path\ P\ a\ b$. By this token $P\ 0$ then corresponds to the type at the
left-endpoint and $P\ 1$ as the type at the right-endpoint. The type is called
$\Path$ because it is connected with paths in homotopy theory. The intuition
behind this is that $\Path$ describes paths in $\MCU$ -- i.e.\ between types. For
a path $p$ for the point $p\ i$ the index $i$ describes how far along the path
one has moved. An inhabitant of $\Path\ P\ a_0\ a_1$ is a (dependent-) function,
$p$, from the index-space to the path space:
$I$ is a special data type called the index set. $I$ can be thought of
simply as the interval on the real numbers from $0$ to $1$. $P$ is a
family of types over the index set $I$. I will sometimes refer to $P$
as the \nomenindex{path space} of some path $p \tp \Path\ P\ a\ b$. By
this token $P\ 0$ then corresponds to the type at the left-endpoint
and $P\ 1$ as the type at the right-endpoint. The type is called
$\Path$ because it is connected with paths in homotopy theory. The
intuition behind this is that $\Path$ describes paths in $\MCU$ --
i.e.\ between types. For a path $p$ for the point $p\ i$ the index $i$
describes how far along the path one has moved. An inhabitant of
$\Path\ P\ a_0\ a_1$ is a (dependent-) function, $p$, from the
index-space to the path space:
%
$$
p \tp \prod_{i \tp I} P\ i
@ -194,7 +195,7 @@ indeed both $\top$ and $\bot$ are propositions:
The term $\varnothing$ is used here to denote an impossible pattern. It is a
theorem that if a mere proposition $A$ is inhabited, then so is it contractible.
If it is not inhabited it is equivalent to the empty-type (or false
proposition).\TODO{Cite!!}
proposition).\TODO{Cite}
I will refer to a type $A \tp \MCU$ as a \emph{mere} proposition if I want to
stress that we have $\isProp\ A$.
@ -242,11 +243,16 @@ Let $\left\Vert A \right\Vert = n$ denote that the level of $A$ is $n$.
Proposition: For any homotopic level $n$ this is a mere proposition.
%
\section{A few lemmas}
Rather than getting into the nitty-gritty details of Agda I venture to take a
more ``combinator-based'' approach. That is, I will use theorems about paths
already that have already been formalized. Specifically the results come from
the Agda library \texttt{cubical} (\TODO{Cite}). I have used a handful of
results from this library as well as contributed a few lemmas myself.\footnote{The module \texttt{Cat.Prelude} lists the upstream dependencies. As well my contribution to \texttt{cubical} can be found in the git logs \TODO{Cite}.}
Rather than getting into the nitty-gritty details of Agda I venture to
take a more ``combinator-based'' approach. That is, I will use
theorems about paths already that have already been formalized.
Specifically the results come from the Agda library \texttt{cubical}
(\cite{cubical-demo}). I have used a handful of results from this
library as well as contributed a few lemmas myself.\footnote{The
module \texttt{Cat.Prelude} lists the upstream dependencies. As well
my contribution to \texttt{cubical} can be found in the git logs
which are available at
\hrefsymb{https://github.com/Saizan/cubical-demo}{\texttt{https://github.com/Saizan/cubical-demo}}.}
These theorems are all purely related to homotopy theory and cubical Agda and as
such not specific to the formalization of Category Theory. I will present a few

View file

@ -97,10 +97,25 @@ a significant impact on the complexity of these kinds of proofs.
\TODO{Universe levels.}
\subsection{Motifs}
An oft-used technique in this development is using based path
induction to prove certain properties. One particular challenge that
arises when doing so is that Agda is not able to automatically infer
the family that one wants to do induction over. For instance in the
proof $\var{sym}\ (\var{sym}\ p) ≡ p$ from \ref{eq:sym-invol} the
family that we chose to do induction over was $D\ b'\ p' \defeq
\var{sym}\ (\var{sym}\ p') ≡ p'$. However, if one interactively tries
to give this hole, all the information that Agda can provide is that
one must provide an element of $𝒰$. Agda could be more helpful in this
context, perhaps even infer this family in some situations. In this
very simple example this is of course not a big problem, but there are
examples in the source code where this gets more involved.
\section{Future work}
\subsection{Agda \texttt{Prop}}
Jesper Cockx' work extending the universe-level-laws for Agda and the
\texttt{Prop}-type.
\TODO{Do I want to include this?}
\subsection{Compiling Cubical Agda}
\label{sec:compiling-cubical-agda}
@ -117,3 +132,8 @@ library exposes could provide one particularly interesting case-study.
\subsection{Higher inductive types}
This library has not explored the usefulness of higher inductive types
in the context of Category Theory.
\subsection{Initiality conjecture}
A fellow student here at Chalmers, Andreas Källberg, is currently
working on proving the initiality conjecture\TODO{Citation}. He will
be using this library to do so.

View file

@ -277,16 +277,19 @@ $i$ becomes the triple:
\end{aligned}
\end{equation}
%
I have found this to be a general pattern when proving things in homotopy type
theory, namely that you have to wrap and unwrap equalities at different levels.
It is worth noting that proving this theorem with the regular inductive equality
type would already not be possible, since we at least need extensionality (the
projections are all $\prod$-types). Assuming we had functional extensionality
available to us as an axiom, we would use functional extensionality \TODO{in
reverse?} to retrieve the equalities in $a$ and $b$, pattern-match on them to
see that they are both $\refl$ and then close the proof with $\refl$.
Of course this theorem is not so interesting in the setting of ITT since we know
a priori that equality proofs are unique.
I have found this to be a general pattern when proving things in
homotopy type theory, namely that you have to wrap and unwrap
equalities at different levels. It is worth noting that proving this
theorem with the regular inductive equality type would already not be
possible, since we at least need functional
extensionality\index{functional extensionality} (the projections are
all $\prod$-types). Assuming we had functional extensionality
available to us as an axiom, we would use functional extensionality
\TODO{in reverse?} to retrieve the equalities in $a$ and $b$,
pattern-match on them to see that they are both $\refl$ and then close
the proof with $\refl$. Of course this theorem is not so interesting
in the setting of ITT since we know a priori that equality proofs are
unique.
The situation is a bit more complicated when we have a dependent type.
For instance, when we want to show that $\IsCategory$ is a mere
@ -326,8 +329,8 @@ $$
And this finishes the proof that being-a-category is a mere proposition
(\ref{eq:propIsPreCategory}).
When we have a proper category we can make precise the notion of ``identifying
isomorphic types'' \TODO{cite Awodey here}. That is, we can construct the
When we have a proper category we can make precise the notion of
``identifying isomorphic types''. That is, we can construct the
function:
%
$$
@ -345,7 +348,11 @@ terminal objects are propositional:
It follows from the usual observation that any two terminal objects are
isomorphic - and since categories are univalent, so are they equal. The proof is
omitted here, but the curious reader can check the implementation for the
details. \TODO{The proof is a bit fun, should I include it?}
details. It is in the module:
%
\begin{center}
\sourcelink{Cat.Category}
\end{center}
\section{Equivalences}
\label{sec:equiv}
@ -744,15 +751,18 @@ the two pairs:
\left( \fst\ u \equiv \fst\ v \right) \to u \equiv v
\end{align*}
%
The proof that these are indeed inverses has been omitted. \TODO{Do I really
want to omit it?}\QED
The proof that these are indeed inverses has been omitted. The details
can be found in the module:
\begin{center}
\sourcelink{Cat.Categories.Sets}
\end{center}
Now to prove \ref{eq:equivSig}: Let $e \tp \prod_{a \tp A} \left( P\ a \simeq
Q\ a \right)$ be given. To prove the equivalence, it suffices to give an
isomorphism between $\sum_{a \tp A} P\ a$ and $\sum_{a \tp A} Q\ a$, but since
they have identical first components it suffices to give an isomorphism between
$P\ a$ and $Q\ a$ for all $a \tp A$. This is exactly what we can get from
the equivalence $e$.\QED
Now to prove \ref{eq:equivSig}: Let $e \tp \prod_{a \tp A} \left( P\ a
\simeq Q\ a \right)$ be given. To prove the equivalence, it suffices
to give an isomorphism between $\sum_{a \tp A} P\ a$ and $\sum_{a \tp
A} Q\ a$, but since they have identical first components it suffices
to give an isomorphism between $P\ a$ and $Q\ a$ for all $a \tp A$.
This is exactly what we can get from the equivalence $e$.\QED
Lastly we prove \ref{eq:equivIso}. Let $f \tp A \to B$ be given. For the maps we
choose:
@ -1050,7 +1060,10 @@ $b_0, b_1$ corresponds to a pair of paths between $a_0,b_0$ and $a_1,b_1$ (check
the implementation for the details).
\emph{Proposition} \ref{eq:univ-1} is isomorphic to \ref{eq:univ-2}:
\TODO{Super complicated}
This proof of this has been omitted but can be found in the module:
\begin{center}
\sourcelink{Cat.Categories.Span}
\end{center}
\emph{Proposition} \ref{eq:univ-2} is isomorphic to \ref{eq:univ-3}: For this I
will show two corollaries of \ref{eq:coeCod}: For an isomorphism $(\iota,
@ -1067,7 +1080,10 @@ f & \equiv g \lll \iota \\
g & \equiv f \lll \inv{\iota}
\end{align}
%
Proof: \TODO{\ldots}
The proof is omitted but can be found in the module:
\begin{center}
\sourcelink{Cat.Category}
\end{center}
Now we can prove the equivalence in the following way: Given $(f, \inv{f},
\var{inv}_f) \tp X \cong Y$ and two heterogeneous paths

View file

@ -207,14 +207,13 @@ implementations of category theory in Agda:
%
The contribution of this thesis is to explore how working in a cubical setting
will make it possible to prove more things and to reuse proofs and to try and
compare some aspects of this formalization with the existing ones.\TODO{How can
I live up to this?}
compare some aspects of this formalization with the existing ones.
There are alternative approaches to working in a cubical setting where
one can still have univalence and functional extensionality. One
option is to postulate these as axioms. This approach, however, has
other shortcomings, e.g. you lose \nomenindex{canonicity}
(\TODO{Pageno!} \cite{huber-2016}).
(\cite[p. 3]{huber-2016}).
Another approach is to use the \emph{setoid interpretation} of type
theory (\cite{hofmann-1995,huber-2016}). With this approach one works
@ -227,16 +226,17 @@ relation a priori. So this must be verified manually by the developer.
Furthermore, functions between different setoids must be shown to be
setoid homomorphism, that is; they preserve the relation.
This approach has other drawbacks; it does not satisfy
all propositional equalities of type theory (\TODO{Citation needed}), is
cumbersome to work with in practice (\cite[p. 4]{huber-2016}) and makes
equational proofs less reusable since equational proofs $a \sim_{X} b$ are
inherently `local' to the extensional set $(X , \sim)$.
This approach has other drawbacks; it does not satisfy all
propositional equalities of type theory a priori. That is, the
developer must manually show that e.g.\ the relation is a congruence.
Equational proofs $a \sim_{X} b$ are in some sense `local' to the
extensional set $(X , \sim)$. To e.g.\ prove that $x y → f\ x
f\ y$ for some function $f \tp A → B$ between two extensional sets $A$
and $B$ it must be shown that $f$ is a groupoid homomorphism. This
makes it very cumbersome to work with in practice (\cite[p.
4]{huber-2016}).
\section{Conventions}
\TODO{Talk a bit about terminology. Find a good place to stuff this little
section.}
In the remainder of this paper I will use the term
\nomenindex{Type} to describe --
well, types. Thereby diverging from the notation in Agda where the keyword