Corrections
This commit is contained in:
parent
2b4ee12ef2
commit
545fb0ade6
|
@ -1,22 +1,7 @@
|
|||
Remove stuff about models of type theory
|
||||
|
||||
Add references to specific (noteable) implementaitons of category theory:
|
||||
* Unimath
|
||||
* cubicaltt
|
||||
* https://github.com/pcapriotti/agda-categories
|
||||
* https://github.com/copumpkin/categories
|
||||
* ...
|
||||
|
||||
Talk about structure of library:
|
||||
===
|
||||
|
||||
Propositional- and non-propositional stuff split up
|
||||
Providing "equiality principles"
|
||||
Provide overview of what has been proven.
|
||||
|
||||
What can I say about reusability?
|
||||
|
||||
Misc
|
||||
====
|
||||
|
||||
Propositional content
|
||||
|
|
|
@ -192,6 +192,7 @@ of these theorems here, as they will be used later in chapter
|
|||
\ref{ch:implementation} throughout.
|
||||
|
||||
\subsection{Path induction}
|
||||
\label{sec:pathJ}
|
||||
The induction principle for paths intuitively gives us a way to reason about a
|
||||
type-family indexed by a path by only considering if said path is $\refl$ (the
|
||||
``base-case''). For \emph{based path induction}, that equaility is \emph{based}
|
||||
|
@ -216,6 +217,7 @@ $$
|
|||
$$
|
||||
%
|
||||
\subsection{Paths over propositions}
|
||||
\label{sec:lemPropF}
|
||||
Another very useful combinator is $\lemPropF$:
|
||||
|
||||
To `promote' this to a dependent path we can use another useful combinator;
|
||||
|
@ -258,6 +260,7 @@ $$
|
|||
$$
|
||||
%
|
||||
\subsection{Functions over propositions}
|
||||
\label{sec:propPi}
|
||||
$\prod$-types preserve propositionality when the co-domain is always a
|
||||
proposition.
|
||||
%
|
||||
|
@ -265,6 +268,7 @@ $$
|
|||
\mathit{propPi} \tp \left(\prod_{a \tp A} \isProp\ (P\ a)\right) \to \isProp\ \left(\prod_{a \tp A} P\ a\right)
|
||||
$$
|
||||
\subsection{Pairs over propositions}
|
||||
\label{sec:propSig}
|
||||
%
|
||||
$\sum$-types preserve propositionality whenever it's first component is a
|
||||
proposition, and it's second component is a proposition for all points of in the
|
||||
|
|
|
@ -42,10 +42,11 @@ Another record encapsulates some laws about this data: associativity of
|
|||
composition, identity law for the identity morphism. These are standard
|
||||
requirements for being a category as can be found in standard mathematical
|
||||
expositions on the topic. We, however, impose one further requirement on what it
|
||||
means to be a category, namely that the type of arrows form a set. We could
|
||||
relax this requirement, this would give us the notion of higher categorier
|
||||
(\cite[p. 307]{hott-2013}). For the purpose of this project, however, this
|
||||
report will restrict itself to 1-categories.
|
||||
means to be a category, namely that the type of arrows form a set. Such
|
||||
categories are called \nomen{1-categories}. We could relax this requirement,
|
||||
this would give us the notion of higher categorier (\cite[p. 307]{hott-2013}).
|
||||
For the purpose of this project, however, this report will restrict itself to
|
||||
1-categories.
|
||||
|
||||
Raw categories satisfying these properties are called a pre-categories.
|
||||
|
||||
|
@ -68,8 +69,9 @@ $$
|
|||
$$
|
||||
%
|
||||
The two types are logically equivalent, however. One can construct the latter
|
||||
from the former simply by ``forgetting'' that $\idToIso$ plays the role
|
||||
of the equivalence. The other direction is more involved.
|
||||
from the former simply by ``forgetting'' that $\idToIso$ plays the role of the
|
||||
equivalence. The other direction is more involved and will be discussed in
|
||||
section \ref{sec:univalence}.
|
||||
|
||||
With all this in place it is now possible to prove that all the laws are indeed
|
||||
mere propositions. Most of the proofs simply use the fact that the type of
|
||||
|
@ -79,28 +81,21 @@ exactly because the type of arrows form a set, two witnesses must be the same.
|
|||
All the proofs are really quite mechanical. Lets have a look at one of them: The
|
||||
identity law states that:
|
||||
%
|
||||
$$
|
||||
\begin{equation}
|
||||
\var{IsIdentity} \defeq
|
||||
\prod_{A\ B \tp \Object} \prod_{f \tp A \to B} \id \comp f \equiv f \x f \comp \id \equiv f
|
||||
$$
|
||||
\end{equation}
|
||||
%
|
||||
There are multiple ways to prove this. Perhaps one of the more intuitive proofs
|
||||
is by way of the following `combinators':
|
||||
is by way of the `combinators' $\propPi$ and $\propSig$ presented in sections
|
||||
\ref{sec:propPi} and \ref{sec:propSig}:
|
||||
%
|
||||
$$
|
||||
\mathit{propPi} \tp \left(\prod_{a \tp A} \isProp\ (P\ a)\right) \to \isProp\ \left(\prod_{a \tp A} P\ a\right)
|
||||
$$
|
||||
\begin{align*}
|
||||
\mathit{propPi} & \tp \left(\prod_{a \tp A} \isProp\ (P\ a)\right) \to \isProp\ \left(\prod_{a \tp A} P\ a\right)
|
||||
\\
|
||||
\mathit{propSig} & \tp \isProp\ A \to \left(\prod_{a \tp A} \isProp\ (P\ a)\right) \to \isProp\ \left(\sum_{a \tp A} P\ a\right)
|
||||
\end{align*}
|
||||
%
|
||||
I.e.; pi-types preserve propositionality when the co-domain is always a
|
||||
proposition.
|
||||
%
|
||||
$$
|
||||
\mathit{propSig} \tp \isProp\ A \to \left(\prod_{a \tp A} \isProp\ (P\ a)\right) \to \isProp\ \left(\sum_{a \tp A} P\ a\right)
|
||||
$$
|
||||
%
|
||||
I.e.; sigma-types preserve propositionality whenever it's first component is a
|
||||
proposition, and it's second component is a proposition for all points of in the
|
||||
left type.
|
||||
|
||||
So the proof goes like this: We `eliminate' the 3 function abstractions by
|
||||
applying $\propPi$ three times. So our proof obligation becomes:
|
||||
%
|
||||
|
@ -135,13 +130,12 @@ $$
|
|||
$$
|
||||
%
|
||||
So let $a\ b \tp \IsPreCategory$ be given. To prove the equality $a \equiv b$ is
|
||||
to give a continuous path from the index-type into path-space - in this case
|
||||
$\IsPreCategory$. This path must satisfy being being judgmentally the same as
|
||||
$a$ at the left endpoint and $b$ at the right endpoint. I.e. a function $I \to
|
||||
\IsPreCategory$. We know we can form a continuous path between all projections
|
||||
of $a$ and $b$, this follows from the type of all the projections being mere
|
||||
propositions. For instance, the path between $\isIdentity_a$ and $\isIdentity_b$
|
||||
is simply formed by:
|
||||
to give a continuous path from the index-type into the path-space. I.e. a
|
||||
function $I \to \IsPreCategory$. This path must satisfy being being judgmentally
|
||||
the same as $a$ at the left endpoint and $b$ at the right endpoint. We know we
|
||||
can form a continuous path between all projections of $a$ and $b$, this follows
|
||||
from the type of all the projections being mere propositions. For instance, the
|
||||
path between $\isIdentity_a$ and $\isIdentity_b$ is simply formed by:
|
||||
%
|
||||
$$
|
||||
\propIsIdentity\ \isIdentity_a\ \isIdentity_b \tp \isIdentity_a \equiv \isIdentity_b
|
||||
|
@ -154,17 +148,18 @@ projections. Once we have such a path e.g. $p \tp \isIdentity_a \equiv
|
|||
\isIdentity_b$ we can elimiate it with $i$ and thus obtaining $p\ i \tp
|
||||
\isIdentity_{p\ i}$ and this element satisfies exactly that it corresponds to
|
||||
the corresponding projections at either endpoint. Thus the element we construct
|
||||
at $i$ becomes:
|
||||
at $i$ becomes the triple:
|
||||
%
|
||||
\begin{align*}
|
||||
& \{\ \mathit{propIsAssociative}\ \mathit{isAssociative}_x\
|
||||
\mathit{isAssociative}_y\ i \\
|
||||
& ,\ \mathit{propIsIdentity}\ \mathit{isIdentity}_x\
|
||||
\mathit{isIdentity}_y\ i \\
|
||||
& ,\ \mathit{propArrowsAreSets}\ \mathit{arrowsAreSets}_x\
|
||||
\mathit{arrowsAreSets}_y\ i \\
|
||||
& \}
|
||||
\end{align*}
|
||||
\begin{equation}
|
||||
\begin{alignat}{4}
|
||||
& \mathit{propIsAssociative} && x.\mathit{isAssociative}\
|
||||
&& y.\mathit{isAssociative} && i \\
|
||||
& \mathit{propIsIdentity} && x.\mathit{isIdentity}\
|
||||
&& y.\mathit{isIdentity} && i \\
|
||||
& \mathit{propArrowsAreSets} && x.\mathit{arrowsAreSets}\
|
||||
&& y.\mathit{arrowsAreSets} && i
|
||||
\end{alignat}
|
||||
\end{equation}
|
||||
%
|
||||
I've found that this to be a general pattern when proving things in homotopy
|
||||
type theory, namely that you have to wrap and unwrap equalities at different
|
||||
|
@ -181,11 +176,11 @@ The situation is a bit more complicated when we have a dependent type. For
|
|||
instance, when we want to show that $\IsCategory$ is a mere proposition.
|
||||
$\IsCategory$ is a record with two fields, a witness to being a pre-category and
|
||||
the univalence condition. Recall that the univalence condition is indexed by the
|
||||
identity-proof. So if we follow the same recipe as above, let $a\ b \tp
|
||||
\IsCategory$, to show them equal, we now need to give two paths. One homogenous:
|
||||
identity-proof. So to follow the same recipe as above, let $a\ b \tp
|
||||
\IsCategory$ be given, to show them equal, we now need to give two paths. One homogenous:
|
||||
%
|
||||
$$
|
||||
p_{\isPreCategory} \tp \isPreCategory_a \equiv \isPreCategory_b
|
||||
p \tp \isPreCategory_a \equiv \isPreCategory_b
|
||||
$$
|
||||
%
|
||||
and one heterogeneous:
|
||||
|
@ -194,29 +189,23 @@ $$
|
|||
\Path\ (\lambda\; i \mto Univalent_{p\ i})\ \isPreCategory_a\ \isPreCategory_b
|
||||
$$
|
||||
%
|
||||
Which depends on the choice of $p_{\isPreCategory}$. The first of these we can
|
||||
provide since, as we have shown, $\IsPreCategory$ is a proposition. However,
|
||||
even though $\Univalent$ is also a proposition, we cannot use this directly to
|
||||
show the latter. This is becasue $\isProp$ talks about non-dependent paths. To
|
||||
`promote' this to a dependent path we can use another useful combinator;
|
||||
$\lemPropF$. Given a type $A \tp \MCU$ and a type family on $A$; $B \tp A \to
|
||||
\MCU$. Let $P$ be a proposition indexed by an element of $A$ and say we have a
|
||||
path between some two elements in $A$; $p \tp a_0 \equiv a_1$ then we can built a
|
||||
heterogeneous path between any two $b$'s at the endpoints:
|
||||
%
|
||||
$$
|
||||
\Path\ (\lambda\; i \mto B\ (p\ i))\ b0\ b1
|
||||
$$
|
||||
%
|
||||
where $b_0 \tp B a_0$ and $b_1 \tp B\ a_1$. This is quite a mouthful, but the
|
||||
example at present should serve as an illustration. In this case $A =
|
||||
\mathit{IsIdentity}\ \mathit{identity}$ and $B = \mathit{Univalent}$ we've shown
|
||||
that being a category is a proposition, a result that holds for any choice of
|
||||
identity proof. Finally we must provide a proof that the identity proofs at $a$
|
||||
and $b$ are indeed the same, this we can extract from $p_{\isPreCategory}$ by
|
||||
applying using congruence of paths: $\congruence\ \mathit{isIdentity}\
|
||||
p_{\isPreCategory}$
|
||||
Which depends on the choice of $p$. The first of these we can provide since, as
|
||||
we have shown, $\IsPreCategory$ is constantly a proposition. However, even
|
||||
though $\Univalent$ is also a proposition, we cannot use this directly to show
|
||||
the latter. This is becasue $\isProp$ talks about non-dependent paths. To
|
||||
`promote' this to a dependent path we can use the combinator; $\lemPropF$
|
||||
introduced in \ref{sec:lemPropF}.
|
||||
|
||||
In this case $A = \mathit{IsIdentity}\ \mathit{identity}$ and $B =
|
||||
\mathit{Univalent}$ we've shown that being a category is a proposition, a result
|
||||
that holds for any choice of identity proof. Finally we must provide a proof
|
||||
that the identity proofs at $a$ and $b$ are indeed the same, this we can extract
|
||||
from $p$ by applying using congruence of paths:
|
||||
%
|
||||
$$
|
||||
\congruence\ \mathit{isIdentity}\ p
|
||||
$$
|
||||
%
|
||||
When we have a proper category we can make precise the notion of ``identifying
|
||||
isomorphic types'' \TODO{cite awodey here}. That is, we can construct the
|
||||
function:
|
||||
|
@ -311,7 +300,7 @@ the type $A \cong B$ as well as the the map $A \to B$ that witness this.
|
|||
Both $\cong$ and $\simeq$ form equivalence relations.
|
||||
|
||||
\section{Univalence}
|
||||
\label{univalence}
|
||||
\label{sec:univalence}
|
||||
As noted in the introduction the univalence for types $A\; B \tp \Type$ states
|
||||
that:
|
||||
%
|
||||
|
@ -342,16 +331,16 @@ equalities and isomorphisms (on arrows). It's worthwhile to dwell on this for a
|
|||
few seconds. This type looks very similar to univalence for types and is
|
||||
therefore perhaps a bit more intuitive to grasp the implications of. Of course
|
||||
univalence for types (which is a proposition -- i.e. provable) does not imply
|
||||
univalence in any category since morphisms in a category are not regular maps --
|
||||
in stead they can be thought of as a generalization hereof; i.e. arrows. The
|
||||
univalence criterion therefore is simply a way of restricting arrows to behave
|
||||
similarly to maps.
|
||||
univalence of all pre-category since morphisms in a category are not regular
|
||||
maps -- in stead they can be thought of as a generalization hereof; i.e. arrows.
|
||||
The univalence criterion therefore is simply a way of restricting arrows to
|
||||
behave similarly to maps.
|
||||
|
||||
I will now mention a few helpful thoerems that follow from univalence that will
|
||||
become useful later.
|
||||
|
||||
Obviously univalence gives us an isomorphism $A \equiv B \to A \approxeq B$. I
|
||||
will name these for convenience:
|
||||
Obviously univalence gives us an isomorphism between $A \equiv B$ and $A
|
||||
\approxeq B$. I will name these for convenience:
|
||||
%
|
||||
$$
|
||||
\idToIso \tp A \equiv B \to A \approxeq B
|
||||
|
@ -366,8 +355,8 @@ an isomorphism $A \approxeq B$ in some category $\bC$ be given. Name the
|
|||
isomorphism $\iota \tp A \to B$ and its inverse $\widetilde{\iota} \tp B \to A$.
|
||||
Since $\bC$ is a category (and therefore univalent) the isomorphism induces a
|
||||
path $p \tp A \equiv B$. From this equality we can get two further paths:
|
||||
$p_{\mathit{dom}} \tp \mathit{Arrow}\ A\ X \equiv \mathit{Arrow}\ A'\ X$ and
|
||||
$p_{\mathit{cod}} \tp \mathit{Arrow}\ X\ A \equiv \mathit{Arrow}\ X\ A'$. We
|
||||
$p_{\mathit{dom}} \tp \mathit{Arrow}\ A\ X \equiv \mathit{Arrow}\ B\ X$ and
|
||||
$p_{\mathit{cod}} \tp \mathit{Arrow}\ X\ A \equiv \mathit{Arrow}\ X\ B$. We
|
||||
then have the following two theorems:
|
||||
%
|
||||
$$
|
||||
|
@ -394,11 +383,11 @@ isomorphism $\mathit{idToIso}\ p \tp A \cong B$. The helper-lemma is similar to
|
|||
what we're trying to prove but talks about paths rather than isomorphisms:
|
||||
%
|
||||
$$
|
||||
\prod_{f \tp \mathit{Arrow}\ A\ B} \prod_{p \tp A \equiv A'} \mathit{coe}\ p^*\ f \equiv f \lll \mathit{obverse}_{\mathit{idToIso}\ p}
|
||||
\prod_{f \tp \mathit{Arrow}\ A\ B} \prod_{p \tp A \equiv B} \mathit{coe}\ p_\var{dom}\ f \equiv f \lll \mathit{obverse}_{\mathit{idToIso}\ p}
|
||||
$$
|
||||
%
|
||||
Note that the asterisk in $p^*$ denotes the path $\mathit{Arrow}\ A\ B \equiv
|
||||
\mathit{Arrow}\ A'\ B$ induced by $p$. To prove this statement I let $f$ and $p$
|
||||
Again $p_\var{dom}$ denotes the path $\mathit{Arrow}\ A\ X \equiv
|
||||
\mathit{Arrow}\ B\ X$ induced by $p$. To prove this statement I let $f$ and $p$
|
||||
be given and then invoke based-path-induction. The induction will be based at $A
|
||||
\tp \mathit{Object}$, so let $\widetilde{A} \tp \Object$ and $\widetilde{p} \tp
|
||||
A \equiv \widetilde{A}$ be given. The family that we perform induction over will
|
||||
|
@ -551,7 +540,7 @@ $$
|
|||
(\mathit{hA} \equiv \mathit{hB}) \simeq (\mathit{hA} \approxeq \mathit{hB})
|
||||
$$
|
||||
%
|
||||
Which, as we saw in section \ref{univalence}, is sufficient to show that the
|
||||
Which, as we saw in section \ref{sec:univalence}, is sufficient to show that the
|
||||
category is univalent. The way that I have shown this is with a three-step
|
||||
process. For objects $(A, s_A)\; (B, s_B) \tp \Set$ I show the following chain
|
||||
of equivalences:
|
||||
|
|
|
@ -70,27 +70,27 @@ The proof obligation that this satisfies the identity law of functors
|
|||
%
|
||||
One needs functional extensionality to ``go under'' the function arrow and apply
|
||||
the (left) identity law of the underlying category to proove $\idFun \comp g
|
||||
\equiv g$ and thus closing the goal.
|
||||
\equiv g$ and thus close the goal.
|
||||
%
|
||||
\subsection{Equality of isomorphic types}
|
||||
%
|
||||
Let $\top$ denote the unit type -- a type with a single constructor. In
|
||||
the propositions-as-types interpretation of type theory $\top$ is the
|
||||
proposition that is always true. The type $A \x \top$ and $A$ has an element for
|
||||
each $a : A$. So in a sense they are the same. The second element of the pair
|
||||
does not add any ``interesting information''. It can be useful to identify such
|
||||
types. In fact, it is quite commonplace in mathematics. Say we look at a set
|
||||
$\{x \mid
|
||||
\phi\ x \land \psi\ x\}$ and somehow conclude that $\psi\ x \equiv \top$ for all
|
||||
$x$. A mathematician would immediately conclude $\{x \mid \phi\ x \land
|
||||
\psi\ x\} \equiv \{x \mid \phi\ x\}$ without thinking twice. Unfortunately such
|
||||
an identification can not be performed in ITT.
|
||||
Let $\top$ denote the unit type -- a type with a single constructor. In the
|
||||
propositions-as-types interpretation of type theory $\top$ is the proposition
|
||||
that is always true. The type $A \x \top$ and $A$ has an element for each $a :
|
||||
A$. So in a sense they have the same shape (greek; \nomen{isomorphic}). The
|
||||
second element of the pair does not add any ``interesting information''. It can
|
||||
be useful to identify such types. In fact, it is quite commonplace in
|
||||
mathematics. Say we look at a set $\{x \mid \phi\ x \land \psi\ x\}$ and somehow
|
||||
conclude that $\psi\ x \equiv \top$ for all $x$. A mathematician would
|
||||
immediately conclude $\{x \mid \phi\ x \land \psi\ x\} \equiv \{x \mid
|
||||
\phi\ x\}$ without thinking twice. Unfortunately such an identification can not
|
||||
be performed in ITT.
|
||||
|
||||
More specifically; what we are interested in is a way of identifying
|
||||
\nomen{equivalent} types. I will return to the definition of equivalence later,
|
||||
but for now, it is sufficient to think of an equivalence as a one-to-one
|
||||
correspondence. We write $A \simeq B$ to assert that $A$ and $B$ are equivalent
|
||||
types. The principle of univalence says that:
|
||||
\nomen{equivalent} types. I will return to the definition of equivalence later
|
||||
in section \ref{sec:equiv}, but for now it is sufficient to think of an
|
||||
equivalence as a one-to-one correspondence. We write $A \simeq B$ to assert that
|
||||
$A$ and $B$ are equivalent types. The principle of univalence says that:
|
||||
%
|
||||
$$\mathit{univalence} \tp (A \simeq B) \simeq (A \equiv B)$$
|
||||
%
|
||||
|
@ -99,14 +99,14 @@ In particular this allows us to construct an equality from an equivalence
|
|||
|
||||
\section{Formalizing Category Theory}
|
||||
%
|
||||
The above examples serve to illustrate the limitation of Agda. One case where
|
||||
these limitations are particularly prohibitive is in the study of Category
|
||||
Theory. At a glance category theory can be described as ``the mathematical study
|
||||
of (abstract) algebras of functions'' (\cite{awodey-2006}). So by that token
|
||||
The above examples serve to illustrate a limitation of ITT. One case where these
|
||||
limitations are particularly prohibitive is in the study of Category Theory. At
|
||||
a glance category theory can be described as ``the mathematical study of
|
||||
(abstract) algebras of functions'' (\cite{awodey-2006}). So by that token
|
||||
functional extensionality is particularly useful for formulating Category
|
||||
Theory. In Category theory it is also common to identify isomorphic structures
|
||||
and this is exactly what we get from univalence. In fact we can formulate this
|
||||
requirement within our formulation of categories by requiring the
|
||||
and univalence gives us a way to make this notion precise. In fact we can
|
||||
formulate this requirement within our formulation of categories by requiring the
|
||||
\emph{categories} themselves to be univalent as we shall see.
|
||||
|
||||
\section{Context}
|
||||
|
@ -117,7 +117,7 @@ Inspiration:
|
|||
* HoTT - sketch of homotopy proofs
|
||||
\end{verbatim}
|
||||
The idea of formalizing Category Theory in proof assistants is not new. There
|
||||
are a multitude of these available online. Just as first reference see this
|
||||
are a multitude of these available online. Just as a first reference see this
|
||||
question on Math Overflow: \cite{mo-formalizations}. Notably these
|
||||
implementations of category theory in Agda:
|
||||
\begin{itemize}
|
||||
|
@ -137,17 +137,17 @@ will make it possible to prove more things and to reuse proofs.
|
|||
There are alternative approaches to working in a cubical setting where one can
|
||||
still have univalence and functional extensionality. One option is to postulate
|
||||
these as axioms. This approach, however, has other shortcomings, e.g.; you lose
|
||||
\nomen{canonicity} (\cite{huber-2016}). Canonicity means that any well-typed
|
||||
term evaluates to a \emph{canonical} form. For example for a closed term $e :
|
||||
\bN$ it will be the case that $e$ reduces to $n$ applications of $\mathit{suc}$
|
||||
to $0$ for some $n$; $e = \mathit{suc}^n\ 0$. Without canonicity terms in the
|
||||
language can get ``stuck'' -- meaning that they do not reduce to a canonical
|
||||
form.
|
||||
\nomen{canonicity} (\TODO{Pageno!} \cite{huber-2016}). Canonicity means that any
|
||||
well-typed term evaluates to a \emph{canonical} form. For example for a closed
|
||||
term $e : \bN$ it will be the case that $e$ reduces to $n$ applications of
|
||||
$\mathit{suc}$ to $0$ for some $n$; $e = \mathit{suc}^n\ 0$. Without canonicity
|
||||
terms in the language can get ``stuck'' -- meaning that they do not reduce to a
|
||||
canonical form.
|
||||
|
||||
Another approach is to use the \emph{setoid interpretation} of type theory
|
||||
(\cite{hofmann-1995,huber-2016}). With this approach one works with
|
||||
\nomen{extensionals sets} $(X, \sim)$, that is a type $X \tp \MCU$ and an
|
||||
equivalence relation $\sim$.
|
||||
equivalence relation $\sim \tp X \to X \to \MCU$.
|
||||
|
||||
Types should additionally `carry around' an equivalence relation that serve as
|
||||
propositional equality. This approach has other drawbacks; it does not satisfy
|
||||
|
|
|
@ -43,14 +43,15 @@
|
|||
\researchgroup{Programming Logic Group}
|
||||
\bibliographystyle{plain}
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
\addtocontents{toc}{\protect\thispagestyle{empty}}
|
||||
\begin{document}
|
||||
|
||||
\pagenumbering{roman}
|
||||
\maketitle
|
||||
|
||||
\tableofcontents
|
||||
%
|
||||
\pagenumbering{arabic}
|
||||
%
|
||||
\input{introduction.tex}
|
||||
\input{cubical.tex}
|
||||
\input{implementation.tex}
|
||||
|
|
Loading…
Reference in a new issue