Add introduction
This commit is contained in:
parent
8a0ea9f4a5
commit
d33c814e78
|
@ -1,8 +1,44 @@
|
|||
\chapter{Introduction}
|
||||
This thesis is a case-study in the application of Cubical Agda in the
|
||||
context of category theory. At the center of this is the notion of
|
||||
\nomenindex{equality}. In type-theory there are two pervasive notions
|
||||
of equality: \nomenindex{judgmental equality} and
|
||||
\nomenindex{propositional equality}. Judgmental equality is a property
|
||||
of the type system, it is a property that is automatically checked by
|
||||
a type checker. As such there are some properties judgmental
|
||||
equalities must crucially have. It must be \nomenindex{decidable},
|
||||
\nomenindex{sound}, enjoy \nomenindex{canonicity} and be a
|
||||
\nomen{congruence relation}. Being decidable simply means that that an
|
||||
algorithm exists to decide whether two terms are equal. For any
|
||||
practical implementation the decidability must also be effectively
|
||||
computable. Soundness means that things judged to be equal actually
|
||||
\emph{are} considered equal. It must be a congruence relation because
|
||||
otherwise the relation certainly does not adhere to our notion of
|
||||
equality. One would be able to conclude things like: $x \nequiv y
|
||||
\rightarrow f\ x \equiv f\ y$. Canonicity will be explained later in
|
||||
this introduction after we've seen an example of judgmental- and
|
||||
propositional equality at play for a simple example.\TODO{How to
|
||||
motivate canonicity for equality}.
|
||||
|
||||
For propositional equality the decidability requirement is relaxed. It
|
||||
is not in general possible to decide the correctness of logical
|
||||
propositions (cf. Hilbert's \nomen{entscheidigungsproblem}).
|
||||
Propositional equality are provided by the developer. When introducing
|
||||
definitions this report will use the notation $\defeq$. Judgmental
|
||||
equalities written $=$. For propositional equalities the notation
|
||||
$\equiv$ is used.
|
||||
|
||||
The usual notion of propositional equality in \nomen{Intensional Type
|
||||
Theory} (ITT) is quite restrictive. In the next section a few
|
||||
motivating examples will highlight this. There exist techniques to
|
||||
circumvent these problems, as we shall see. This thesis will explore
|
||||
an extension to Agda that redefines the notion of propositional
|
||||
equality and as such is an alternative to these other techniques.
|
||||
%
|
||||
\section{Motivating examples}
|
||||
%
|
||||
In the following two sections I present two examples that illustrate some
|
||||
limitations inherent in ITT and -- by extension -- Agda.
|
||||
In the following two sections I present two examples that illustrate
|
||||
some limitations inherent in ITT and -- by extension -- Agda.
|
||||
%
|
||||
\subsection{Functional extensionality}
|
||||
\label{sec:functional-extensionality}%
|
||||
|
@ -18,9 +54,9 @@ Consider the functions:
|
|||
\end{equation*}%
|
||||
\end{multicols}%
|
||||
%
|
||||
The term $n + 0$ is
|
||||
The term $n + 0$ is
|
||||
\nomenindex{definitionally} equal to $n$, which we
|
||||
write as $n + 0 = n$. This is also called
|
||||
write as $n + 0 = n$. This is also called
|
||||
\nomenindex{judgmental equality}.
|
||||
We call it definitional equality because the \emph{equality} arises
|
||||
from the \emph{definition} of $+$ which is:
|
||||
|
@ -39,35 +75,43 @@ as $n + 0 \equiv n$. Propositional equality means that there is a
|
|||
proof that exhibits this relation. Since equality is a transitive
|
||||
relation we have that $n + 0 \equiv 0 + n$.
|
||||
|
||||
Unfortunately we don't have $f \equiv g$.\footnote{Actually showing this is
|
||||
outside the scope of this text. Essentially it would involve giving a model
|
||||
for our type theory that validates all our axioms but where $f \equiv g$ is
|
||||
not true.} There is no way to construct a proof asserting the obvious
|
||||
equivalence of $f$ and $g$ -- even though we can prove them equal for all
|
||||
points. This is exactly the notion of equality of functions that we are
|
||||
interested in; that they are equal for all inputs. We call this
|
||||
Unfortunately we don't have $f \equiv g$. There is no way to construct
|
||||
a proof asserting the obvious equivalence of $f$ and $g$. Actually
|
||||
showing this is outside the scope of this text. Essentially it would
|
||||
involve giving a model for our type theory that validates all our
|
||||
axioms but where $f \equiv g$ is not true. We cannot show that they
|
||||
are equal, even though we can prove them equal for all points. For
|
||||
functions this is exactly the notion of equality that we are
|
||||
interested in: Functions are considered equal when they are equal for
|
||||
all inputs. This is called \nomenindex{point wise equality}, where the
|
||||
\emph{points} of a function refer to its arguments.
|
||||
|
||||
\nomenindex{point-wise equality}, where the \emph{points} of a function refers
|
||||
to its arguments.
|
||||
|
||||
In the context of category theory functional extensionality is e.g. needed to
|
||||
show that representable functors are indeed functors. The representable functor
|
||||
for a category $\bC$ and a fixed object in $A \in \bC$ is defined to be:
|
||||
%
|
||||
\begin{align*}
|
||||
\fmap \defeq \lambda\ X \to \Hom_{\bC}(A, X)
|
||||
\end{align*}
|
||||
%
|
||||
The proof obligation that this satisfies the identity law of functors
|
||||
($\fmap\ \idFun \equiv \idFun$) thus becomes:
|
||||
%
|
||||
\begin{align*}
|
||||
\Hom(A, \idFun_{\bX}) = (\lambda\ g \to \idFun \comp g) \equiv \idFun_{\Sets}
|
||||
\end{align*}
|
||||
%
|
||||
One needs functional extensionality to ``go under'' the function arrow and apply
|
||||
the (left) identity law of the underlying category to prove $\idFun \comp g
|
||||
\equiv g$ and thus close the goal.
|
||||
%% In the context of category theory functional extensionality is e.g.
|
||||
%% needed to show that representable functors are indeed functors. The
|
||||
%% representable functor is defined for a fixed category $\bC$ and an
|
||||
%% object $X \in \bC$. It's map on objects is defined thus:
|
||||
%% %
|
||||
%% \begin{align*}
|
||||
%% \lambda\ A \to \Arrow\ X\ A
|
||||
%% \end{align*}
|
||||
%% %
|
||||
%% That is, it maps objects to arrows. So, it's map on arrows must map an arrow $\Arrow\ A\ B$ to an
|
||||
%% The map on objects is defined thus:
|
||||
%% %
|
||||
%% \begin{align*}
|
||||
%% \lambda f \to
|
||||
%% \end{align*}
|
||||
%% %
|
||||
%% The proof obligation that this satisfies the identity law of functors
|
||||
%% ($\fmap\ \idFun \equiv \idFun$) thus becomes:
|
||||
%% %
|
||||
%% \begin{align*}
|
||||
%% \Hom(A, \idFun_{\bX}) = (\lambda\ g \to \idFun \comp g) \equiv \idFun_{\Sets}
|
||||
%% \end{align*}
|
||||
%% %
|
||||
%% One needs functional extensionality to ``go under'' the function arrow and apply
|
||||
%% the (left) identity law of the underlying category to prove $\idFun \comp g
|
||||
%% \equiv g$ and thus close the goal.
|
||||
%
|
||||
\subsection{Equality of isomorphic types}
|
||||
%
|
||||
|
@ -75,7 +119,7 @@ Let $\top$ denote the unit type -- a type with a single constructor.
|
|||
In the propositions as types interpretation of type theory $\top$ is
|
||||
the proposition that is always true. The type $A \x \top$ and $A$ has
|
||||
an element for each $a \tp A$. So in a sense they have the same shape
|
||||
(Greek;
|
||||
(Greek;
|
||||
\nomenindex{isomorphic}). The second element of the pair does not
|
||||
add any ``interesting information''. It can be useful to identify such
|
||||
types. In fact, it is quite commonplace in mathematics. Say we look at
|
||||
|
@ -87,10 +131,11 @@ be performed in ITT.
|
|||
|
||||
More specifically what we are interested in is a way of identifying
|
||||
|
||||
\nomenindex{equivalent} types. I will return to the definition of equivalence later
|
||||
in section \S\ref{sec:equiv}, but for now it is sufficient to think of an
|
||||
equivalence as a one-to-one correspondence. We write $A \simeq B$ to assert that
|
||||
$A$ and $B$ are equivalent types. The principle of univalence says that:
|
||||
\nomenindex{equivalent} types. I will return to the definition of
|
||||
equivalence later in section \S\ref{sec:equiv}, but for now it is
|
||||
sufficient to think of an equivalence as a one-to-one correspondence.
|
||||
We write $A \simeq B$ to assert that $A$ and $B$ are equivalent types.
|
||||
The principle of univalence says that:
|
||||
%
|
||||
$$\mathit{univalence} \tp (A \simeq B) \simeq (A \equiv B)$$
|
||||
%
|
||||
|
@ -119,25 +164,20 @@ implementations of category theory in Agda:
|
|||
%
|
||||
\begin{itemize}
|
||||
\item
|
||||
A formalization in Agda using the setoid approach:
|
||||
\url{https://github.com/copumpkin/categories}
|
||||
|
||||
A formalization in Agda using the setoid approach
|
||||
\item
|
||||
A formalization in Agda with univalence and functional
|
||||
extensionality as postulates:
|
||||
\url{https://github.com/pcapriotti/agda-categories}
|
||||
|
||||
A formalization in Agda with univalence and functional extensionality as
|
||||
postulates.
|
||||
\item
|
||||
A formalization in Coq in the homotopic setting:
|
||||
\url{https://github.com/HoTT/HoTT/tree/master/theories/Categories}
|
||||
|
||||
A formalization in Coq in the homotopic setting
|
||||
\item
|
||||
\url{https://github.com/mortberg/cubicaltt}
|
||||
|
||||
A formalization in CubicalTT - a language designed for cubical type theory.
|
||||
Formalizes many different things, but only a few concepts from category
|
||||
theory.
|
||||
|
||||
theory:
|
||||
\url{https://github.com/mortberg/cubicaltt}
|
||||
\end{itemize}
|
||||
%
|
||||
The contribution of this thesis is to explore how working in a cubical setting
|
||||
|
@ -158,7 +198,7 @@ canonical form.
|
|||
|
||||
Another approach is to use the \emph{setoid interpretation} of type
|
||||
theory (\cite{hofmann-1995,huber-2016}). With this approach one works
|
||||
with
|
||||
with
|
||||
\nomenindex{extensional sets} $(X, \sim)$, that is a type $X \tp \MCU$
|
||||
and an equivalence relation $\sim\ \tp X \to X \to \MCU$ on that type.
|
||||
Under the setoid interpretation the equivalence relation serve as a
|
||||
|
@ -178,18 +218,18 @@ inherently `local' to the extensional set $(X , \sim)$.
|
|||
\TODO{Talk a bit about terminology. Find a good place to stuff this little
|
||||
section.}
|
||||
|
||||
In the remainder of this paper I will use the term
|
||||
In the remainder of this paper I will use the term
|
||||
\nomenindex{Type} to describe --
|
||||
well, types. Thereby diverging from the notation in Agda where the keyword
|
||||
\texttt{Set} refers to types.
|
||||
\texttt{Set} refers to types.
|
||||
\nomenindex{Set} on the other hand shall refer to the
|
||||
homotopical notion of a set. I will also leave all universe levels implicit.
|
||||
|
||||
And I use the term
|
||||
And I use the term
|
||||
\nomenindex{arrow} to refer to morphisms in a category,
|
||||
whereas the terms
|
||||
\nomenindex{morphism},
|
||||
\nomenindex{map} or
|
||||
whereas the terms
|
||||
\nomenindex{morphism},
|
||||
\nomenindex{map} or
|
||||
\nomenindex{function}
|
||||
shall be reserved for talking about type theoretic functions; i.e.
|
||||
functions in Agda.
|
||||
|
|
Loading…
Reference in a new issue