Always use brackets in subscript
This commit is contained in:
parent
4070e702d7
commit
d5a4550ca9
|
@ -72,7 +72,7 @@ endpoints. I.e.:
|
||||||
\begin{align*}
|
\begin{align*}
|
||||||
p\ 0 & = a_0 \\
|
p\ 0 & = a_0 \\
|
||||||
p\ 1 & = a_1
|
p\ 1 & = a_1
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align*}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
The notion of ``homogeneous equalities'' can be recovered by not letting the
|
The notion of ``homogeneous equalities'' can be recovered by not letting the
|
||||||
path-space $P$ depend on it's argument:
|
path-space $P$ depend on it's argument:
|
||||||
|
|
|
@ -208,14 +208,14 @@ corresponding projections at either endpoint. Thus the element we construct at
|
||||||
$i$ becomes the triple:
|
$i$ becomes the triple:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{equation}
|
\begin{equation}
|
||||||
\begin{alignat}{4}
|
\begin{aligned}
|
||||||
& \var{propIsAssociative} && a.\var{isAssociative}\
|
& \var{propIsAssociative} && a.\var{isAssociative}\
|
||||||
&& b.\var{isAssociative} && i \\
|
&& b.\var{isAssociative} && i \\
|
||||||
& \var{propIsIdentity} && a.\var{isIdentity}\
|
& \var{propIsIdentity} && a.\var{isIdentity}\
|
||||||
&& b.\var{isIdentity} && i \\
|
&& b.\var{isIdentity} && i \\
|
||||||
& \var{propArrowsAreSets} && a.\var{arrowsAreSets}\
|
& \var{propArrowsAreSets} && a.\var{arrowsAreSets}\
|
||||||
&& b.\var{arrowsAreSets} && i
|
&& b.\var{arrowsAreSets} && i
|
||||||
\end{alignat}
|
\end{aligned}
|
||||||
\end{equation}
|
\end{equation}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
I've found this to be a general pattern when proving things in homotopy type
|
I've found this to be a general pattern when proving things in homotopy type
|
||||||
|
@ -444,10 +444,10 @@ what we're trying to prove but talks about paths rather than isomorphisms:
|
||||||
\begin{equation}
|
\begin{equation}
|
||||||
\label{eq:coeDomIso}
|
\label{eq:coeDomIso}
|
||||||
\prod_{f \tp \var{Arrow}\ A\ B} \prod_{p \tp A \equiv B}
|
\prod_{f \tp \var{Arrow}\ A\ B} \prod_{p \tp A \equiv B}
|
||||||
\var{coe}\ p_\var{dom}\ f \equiv f \lll \inv{(\var{idToIso}\ p)}}
|
\var{coe}\ p_{\var{dom}}\ f \equiv f \lll \inv{(\var{idToIso}\ p)}
|
||||||
\end{equation}
|
\end{equation}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Again $p_\var{dom}$ denotes the path $\var{Arrow}\ A\ X \equiv
|
Again $p_{\var{dom}}$ denotes the path $\var{Arrow}\ A\ X \equiv
|
||||||
\var{Arrow}\ B\ X$ induced by $p$. To prove this statement I let $f$ and $p$
|
\var{Arrow}\ B\ X$ induced by $p$. To prove this statement I let $f$ and $p$
|
||||||
be given and then invoke based-path-induction. The induction will be based at $A
|
be given and then invoke based-path-induction. The induction will be based at $A
|
||||||
\tp \var{Object}$, so let $\widetilde{B} \tp \Object$ and $\widetilde{p} \tp
|
\tp \var{Object}$, so let $\widetilde{B} \tp \Object$ and $\widetilde{p} \tp
|
||||||
|
@ -652,12 +652,15 @@ First, lets proove \ref{eq:equivPropSig}: Let $propP \tp \prod_{a \tp A} \isProp
|
||||||
of $\var{fromIsomorphism}$ it suffices to give an isomorphism between
|
of $\var{fromIsomorphism}$ it suffices to give an isomorphism between
|
||||||
$x \equiv y$ and $\fst\ x \equiv \fst\ y$:
|
$x \equiv y$ and $\fst\ x \equiv \fst\ y$:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{alignat*}{5}
|
%% FIXME: Too much alignement?
|
||||||
|
\begin{equation*}
|
||||||
|
\begin{aligned}
|
||||||
f & \defeq \congruence\ \fst
|
f & \defeq \congruence\ \fst
|
||||||
&& \tp x && \equiv y && \to \fst\ x && \equiv \fst\ y \\
|
&& \tp x \equiv y && \to \fst\ x \equiv \fst\ y \\
|
||||||
g & \defeq \var{lemSig}\ \var{propP}\ x\ y
|
g & \defeq \var{lemSig}\ \var{propP}\ x\ y
|
||||||
&& \tp \fst\ x && \equiv \fst\ y && \to x && \equiv y
|
&& \tp \fst\ x \equiv \fst\ y && \to x \equiv y
|
||||||
\end{alignat*}
|
\end{aligned}
|
||||||
|
\end{equation*}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\TODO{Is it confusing that I use point-free style here?} Here $\var{lemSig}$ is
|
\TODO{Is it confusing that I use point-free style here?} Here $\var{lemSig}$ is
|
||||||
a lemma that says that if the second component of a pair is a proposition, it
|
a lemma that says that if the second component of a pair is a proposition, it
|
||||||
|
@ -856,15 +859,15 @@ Which is provable by \TODO{What?} and that the witness to \ref{eq:pairArrowLaw}
|
||||||
for the left-hand-side and the right-hand-side are the same. The type of this
|
for the left-hand-side and the right-hand-side are the same. The type of this
|
||||||
goal is quite involved, and I will not write it out in full, but at present it
|
goal is quite involved, and I will not write it out in full, but at present it
|
||||||
suffices to show the type of the path-space. Note that the arrows in
|
suffices to show the type of the path-space. Note that the arrows in
|
||||||
\ref{eq:productAssoc} are arrows from $\mathcal{A} = (A , a_\pairA , a_\pairB)$
|
\ref{eq:productAssoc} are arrows from $\mathcal{A} = (A , a_{\pairA} , a_{\pairB})$
|
||||||
to $\mathcal{D} = (D , d_\pairA , d_\pairB)$ where $a_\pairA$, $a_\pairB$,
|
to $\mathcal{D} = (D , d_{\pairA} , d_{\pairB})$ where $a_{\pairA}$, $a_{\pairB}$,
|
||||||
$d_\pairA$ and $d_\pairB$ are arrows in the underlying category. Given that $p$
|
$d_{\pairA}$ and $d_{\pairB}$ are arrows in the underlying category. Given that $p$
|
||||||
is the chosen proof of \ref{eq:productAssocUnderlying} we then have that the
|
is the chosen proof of \ref{eq:productAssocUnderlying} we then have that the
|
||||||
witness to \ref{eq:pairArrowLaw} vary over the type:
|
witness to \ref{eq:pairArrowLaw} vary over the type:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
\label{eq:productPath}
|
\label{eq:productPath}
|
||||||
λ\ i → d_\pairA \lll p\ i ≡ a_\pairA × d_\pairB \lll p\ i ≡ a_\pairB
|
λ\ i → d_{\pairA} \lll p\ i ≡ 2 a_{\pairA} × d_{\pairB} \lll p\ i ≡ a_{\pairB}
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
And these paths are in the type of the hom-set of the underlying category, so
|
And these paths are in the type of the hom-set of the underlying category, so
|
||||||
|
@ -874,14 +877,14 @@ stead we generalize \ref{eq:productPath} to:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
\label{eq:productEqPrinc}
|
\label{eq:productEqPrinc}
|
||||||
\prod_{f \tp \Arrow\ X\ Y} \isProp\ \left( y_\pairA \lll f ≡ x_\pairA × y_\pairB \lll f ≡ x_\pairB \right)
|
\prod_{f \tp \Arrow\ X\ Y} \isProp\ \left( y_{\pairA} \lll f ≡ x_{\pairA} × y_{\pairB} \lll f ≡ x_{\pairB} \right)
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
For all objects $X , x_\pairA , x_\pairB$ and $Y , y_\pairA , y_\pairB$, but
|
For all objects $X , x_{\pairA} , x_{\pairB}$ and $Y , y_{\pairA} , y_{\pairB}$,
|
||||||
this follows from pairs preserving homotopical structure and arrows in the
|
but this follows from pairs preserving homotopical structure and arrows in the
|
||||||
underlying category being sets. This gives us an equality principle for arrows
|
underlying category being sets. This gives us an equality principle for arrows
|
||||||
in this category that says that to prove two arrows $f, f_0, f_1$ and $g, g_0,
|
in this category that says that to prove two arrows $f, f_0, f_1$ and $g, g_0,
|
||||||
$g_1$ equal it suffices to give a proof that $f$ and $g$ are equal.
|
g_1$ equal it suffices to give a proof that $f$ and $g$ are equal.
|
||||||
%% %
|
%% %
|
||||||
%% $$
|
%% $$
|
||||||
%% \prod_{(f, f_0, f_1)\; (g,g_0,g_1) \tp \Arrow\ X\ Y} f \equiv g \to (f, f_0, f_1) \equiv (g,g_0,g_1)
|
%% \prod_{(f, f_0, f_1)\; (g,g_0,g_1) \tp \Arrow\ X\ Y} f \equiv g \to (f, f_0, f_1) \equiv (g,g_0,g_1)
|
||||||
|
@ -899,13 +902,16 @@ $$
|
||||||
Since pairs preserve homotopical structure this reduces to:
|
Since pairs preserve homotopical structure this reduces to:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
\isSet\ (\Arrow_\bC\ X\ Y)
|
\isSet\ (\Arrow_{\bC}\ X\ Y)
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Which holds. And
|
Which holds. And
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
\prod_{f \tp \Arrow\ X\ Y} \isSet\ \left( y_\pairA \lll f ≡ x_\pairA × y_\pairB \lll f ≡ x_\pairB \right)
|
\prod_{f \tp \Arrow\ X\ Y}
|
||||||
|
\isSet\ \left( y_{\pairA} \lll f ≡ x_{\pairA}
|
||||||
|
× y_{\pairB} \lll f ≡ x_{\pairB}
|
||||||
|
\right)
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
This we get from \ref{eq:productEqPrinc} and the fact that homotopical structure
|
This we get from \ref{eq:productEqPrinc} and the fact that homotopical structure
|
||||||
|
@ -915,8 +921,8 @@ This finishes the proof that this is a valid pre-category.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\subsubsection{Univalence}
|
\subsubsection{Univalence}
|
||||||
To prove that this is a proper category it must be shown that it is univalent.
|
To prove that this is a proper category it must be shown that it is univalent.
|
||||||
That is, for any two objects $\mathcal{X} = (X, x_\mathcal{A} , x_\mathca{B})$
|
That is, for any two objects $\mathcal{X} = (X, x_{\mathcal{A}} , x_{\mathcal{B}})$
|
||||||
and $\mathcal{Y} = Y, y_\mathcal{A}, y_\mathcal{B}$ I will show:
|
and $\mathcal{Y} = Y, y_{\mathcal{A}}, y_{\mathcal{B}}$ I will show:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
(\mathcal{X} \equiv \mathcal{Y}) \cong (\mathcal{X} \approxeq \mathcal{Y})
|
(\mathcal{X} \equiv \mathcal{Y}) \cong (\mathcal{X} \approxeq \mathcal{Y})
|
||||||
|
@ -928,7 +934,7 @@ The first type is:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
\label{eq:univ-0}
|
\label{eq:univ-0}
|
||||||
(X , x_\mathcal{A} , x_\mathcal{B}) ≡ (Y , y_\mathcal{A} , y_\mathcal{B})
|
(X , x_{\mathcal{A}} , x_{\mathcal{B}}) ≡ (Y , y_{\mathcal{A}} , y_{\mathcal{B}})
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
The next types will be the triple:
|
The next types will be the triple:
|
||||||
|
@ -937,8 +943,8 @@ The next types will be the triple:
|
||||||
\label{eq:univ-1}
|
\label{eq:univ-1}
|
||||||
\begin{split}
|
\begin{split}
|
||||||
p \tp & X \equiv Y \\
|
p \tp & X \equiv Y \\
|
||||||
& \Path\ (λ i → \Arrow\ (p\ i)\ \mathcal{A})\ x_\mathcal{A}\ y_\mathcal{A} \\
|
& \Path\ (λ i → \Arrow\ (p\ i)\ \mathcal{A})\ x_{\mathcal{A}}\ y_{\mathcal{A}} \\
|
||||||
& \Path\ (λ i → \Arrow\ (p\ i)\ \mathcal{B})\ x_\mathcal{B}\ y_\mathcal{B}
|
& \Path\ (λ i → \Arrow\ (p\ i)\ \mathcal{B})\ x_{\mathcal{B}}\ y_{\mathcal{B}}
|
||||||
\end{split}
|
\end{split}
|
||||||
%% \end{split}
|
%% \end{split}
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
|
@ -950,8 +956,8 @@ isomorphism, and create a path from this:
|
||||||
\label{eq:univ-2}
|
\label{eq:univ-2}
|
||||||
\begin{split}
|
\begin{split}
|
||||||
\var{iso} \tp & X \cong Y \\
|
\var{iso} \tp & X \cong Y \\
|
||||||
& \Path\ (λ i → \Arrow\ (\widetilde{p}\ i)\ \mathcal{A})\ x_\mathcal{A}\ y_\mathcal{A} \\
|
& \Path\ (λ i → \Arrow\ (\widetilde{p}\ i)\ \mathcal{A})\ x_{\mathcal{A}}\ y_{\mathcal{A}} \\
|
||||||
& \Path\ (λ i → \Arrow\ (\widetilde{p}\ i)\ \mathcal{B})\ x_\mathcal{B}\ y_\mathcal{B}
|
& \Path\ (λ i → \Arrow\ (\widetilde{p}\ i)\ \mathcal{B})\ x_{\mathcal{B}}\ y_{\mathcal{B}}
|
||||||
\end{split}
|
\end{split}
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
|
@ -961,7 +967,7 @@ Finally we have the type:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
\label{eq:univ-3}
|
\label{eq:univ-3}
|
||||||
(X , x_\mathcal{A} , x_\mathcal{B}) ≊ (Y , y_\mathcal{A} , y_\mathcal{B})
|
(X , x_{\mathcal{A}} , x_{\mathcal{B}}) ≊ (Y , y_{\mathcal{A}} , y_{\mathcal{B}})
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\emph{Proposition} \ref{eq:univ-0} is isomorphic to \ref{eq:univ-1}: This is
|
\emph{Proposition} \ref{eq:univ-0} is isomorphic to \ref{eq:univ-1}: This is
|
||||||
|
@ -976,7 +982,7 @@ the implementation for the details).
|
||||||
will swho two corrolaries of \ref{eq:coeCod}: For an isomorphism $(\iota,
|
will swho two corrolaries of \ref{eq:coeCod}: For an isomorphism $(\iota,
|
||||||
\inv{\iota}, \var{inv}) \tp A \cong B$, arrows $f \tp \Arrow\ A\ X$, $g \tp
|
\inv{\iota}, \var{inv}) \tp A \cong B$, arrows $f \tp \Arrow\ A\ X$, $g \tp
|
||||||
\Arrow\ B\ X$ and a heterogeneous path between them, $q \tp \Path\ (\lambda i
|
\Arrow\ B\ X$ and a heterogeneous path between them, $q \tp \Path\ (\lambda i
|
||||||
\to p_\var{dom}\ i)\ f\ g$, where $p_\var{dom} \tp \Arrow\ A\ X \equiv
|
\to p_{\var{dom}}\ i)\ f\ g$, where $p_{\var{dom}} \tp \Arrow\ A\ X \equiv
|
||||||
\Arrow\ B\ X$ is a path induced by $\var{iso}$, we have the following two
|
\Arrow\ B\ X$ is a path induced by $\var{iso}$, we have the following two
|
||||||
results
|
results
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
|
@ -993,14 +999,14 @@ Now we can prove the equiavalence in the following way: Given $(f, \inv{f},
|
||||||
\var{inv}_f) \tp X \cong Y$ and two heterogeneous paths
|
\var{inv}_f) \tp X \cong Y$ and two heterogeneous paths
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align*}
|
\begin{align*}
|
||||||
p_\mathcal{A} & \tp \Path\ (\lambda i \to p_\var{dom}\ i)\ x_\mathcal{A}\ y_\mathcal{A}\\
|
p_{\mathcal{A}} & \tp \Path\ (\lambda i \to p_{\var{dom}}\ i)\ x_{\mathcal{A}}\ y_{\mathcal{A}}\\
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
q_\mathcal{B} & \tp \Path\ (\lambda i \to p_\var{dom}\ i)\ x_\mathcal{B}\ y_\mathcal{B}
|
q_{\mathcal{B}} & \tp \Path\ (\lambda i \to p_{\var{dom}}\ i)\ x_{\mathcal{B}}\ y_{\mathcal{B}}
|
||||||
\end{align*}
|
\end{align*}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
all as in \ref{eq:univ-2}. I use $p_\var{dom}$ here again to mean the path
|
all as in \ref{eq:univ-2}. I use $p_{\var{dom}}$ here again to mean the path
|
||||||
induced by the isomorphism $f, \inv{f}$. I must now construct an isomorphism
|
induced by the isomorphism $f, \inv{f}$. I must now construct an isomorphism
|
||||||
$(X, x_\mathcal{A}, x_\mathcal{B}) \approxeq (Y, y_\mathcal{A}, y_\mathcal{B}$
|
$(X, x_{\mathcal{A}}, x_{\mathcal{B}}) \approxeq (Y, y_{\mathcal{A}}, y_{\mathcal{B}})$
|
||||||
as in \ref{eq:univ-3}. That is, an isomorphism in the present category. I remind
|
as in \ref{eq:univ-3}. That is, an isomorphism in the present category. I remind
|
||||||
the reader that such a gadget is a triple. The first component shall be:
|
the reader that such a gadget is a triple. The first component shall be:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
|
@ -1012,10 +1018,10 @@ To show that this choice fits the bill I must now verify that it satisfies
|
||||||
\ref{eq:pairArrowLaw}, which in this case becomes:
|
\ref{eq:pairArrowLaw}, which in this case becomes:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
y_\mathcal{A} \lll f ≡ x_\mathcal{A} × y_\mathcal{B} \lll f ≡ x_\mathcal{B}
|
y_{\mathcal{A}} \lll f ≡ x_{\mathcal{A}} × y_{\mathcal{B}} \lll f ≡ x_{\mathcal{B}}
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Which, since $f$ is an isomorphism and $p_\mathcal{A}$ (resp. $p_\mathcal{B}$)
|
Which, since $f$ is an isomorphism and $p_{\mathcal{A}}$ (resp. $p_{\mathcal{B}}$)
|
||||||
is a path varying according to a path constructed from this isomorphism, this is
|
is a path varying according to a path constructed from this isomorphism, this is
|
||||||
exactly what \ref{eq:domain-twist-0} gives us.
|
exactly what \ref{eq:domain-twist-0} gives us.
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
|
@ -1033,7 +1039,7 @@ For the other direction we're given just given the isomorphism
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
(f, \inv{f}, \var{inv}_f)
|
(f, \inv{f}, \var{inv}_f)
|
||||||
\tp
|
\tp
|
||||||
(X, x_\mathcal{A}, x_\mathcal{B}) \approxeq (Y, y_\mathcal{A}, y_\mathcal{B})
|
(X, x_{\mathcal{A}}, x_{\mathcal{B}}) \approxeq (Y, y_{\mathcal{A}}, y_{\mathcal{B}})
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
Projecting out the first component gives us the isomorphism
|
Projecting out the first component gives us the isomorphism
|
||||||
|
@ -1048,8 +1054,8 @@ This gives rise to the following paths:
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
\begin{split}
|
\begin{split}
|
||||||
\widetilde{p} & \tp X \equiv Y \\
|
\widetilde{p} & \tp X \equiv Y \\
|
||||||
\widetilde{p}_\mathcal{A} & \tp \Arrow\ X\ \mathcal{A} \equiv \Arrow\ Y\ \mathcal{A} \\
|
\widetilde{p}_{\mathcal{A}} & \tp \Arrow\ X\ \mathcal{A} \equiv \Arrow\ Y\ \mathcal{A} \\
|
||||||
\widetilde{p}_\mathcal{B} & \tp \Arrow\ X\ \mathcal{B} \equiv \Arrow\ Y\ \mathcal{B}
|
\widetilde{p}_{\mathcal{B}} & \tp \Arrow\ X\ \mathcal{B} \equiv \Arrow\ Y\ \mathcal{B}
|
||||||
\end{split}
|
\end{split}
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
|
@ -1058,8 +1064,8 @@ It then remains to construct the two paths:
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
\begin{split}
|
\begin{split}
|
||||||
\label{eq:product-paths}
|
\label{eq:product-paths}
|
||||||
& \Path\ (λ i → \widetilde{p}_\mathcal{A}\ i)\ x_\mathcal{A}\ y_\mathcal{A}\\
|
& \Path\ (λ i → \widetilde{p}_{\mathcal{A}}\ i)\ x_{\mathcal{A}}\ y_{\mathcal{A}}\\
|
||||||
& \Path\ (λ i → \widetilde{p}_\mathcal{B}\ i)\ x_\mathcal{B}\ y_\mathcal{B}
|
& \Path\ (λ i → \widetilde{p}_{\mathcal{B}}\ i)\ x_{\mathcal{B}}\ y_{\mathcal{B}}
|
||||||
\end{split}
|
\end{split}
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
|
@ -1077,17 +1083,17 @@ Which is used without proof. See the implementation for the details.
|
||||||
\begin{align}
|
\begin{align}
|
||||||
\begin{split}
|
\begin{split}
|
||||||
\label{eq:product-paths}
|
\label{eq:product-paths}
|
||||||
\var{coe}\ \widetilde{p}_\mathcal{A}\ x_\mathcal{A} ≡ y_\mathcal{A}\\
|
\var{coe}\ \widetilde{p}_{\mathcal{A}}\ x_{\mathcal{A}} ≡ y_{\mathcal{A}}\\
|
||||||
\var{coe}\ \widetilde{p}_\mathcal{B}\ x_\mathcal{B} ≡ y_\mathcal{B}
|
\var{coe}\ \widetilde{p}_{\mathcal{B}}\ x_{\mathcal{B}} ≡ y_{\mathcal{B}}
|
||||||
\end{split}
|
\end{split}
|
||||||
\end{align}
|
\end{align}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
The proof of the first one is:
|
The proof of the first one is:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{align*}
|
\begin{align*}
|
||||||
\var{coe}\ \widetilde{p}_\mathcal{A}\ x_\mathcal{A}
|
\var{coe}\ \widetilde{p}_{\mathcal{A}}\ x_{\mathcal{A}}
|
||||||
& ≡ x_\mathcal{A} \lll \fst\ \inv{f} && \text{$\var{coeDom}$ and the isomorphism $f, \inv{f}$} \\
|
& ≡ x_{\mathcal{A}} \lll \fst\ \inv{f} && \text{$\var{coeDom}$ and the isomorphism $f, \inv{f}$} \\
|
||||||
& ≡ y_\mathcal{A} && \text{\ref{eq:pairArrowLaw} for $\inv{f}$}
|
& ≡ y_{\mathcal{A}} && \text{\ref{eq:pairArrowLaw} for $\inv{f}$}
|
||||||
\end{align*}
|
\end{align*}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
We have now constructed the maps between \ref{eq:univ-0} and \ref{eq:univ-1}. It
|
We have now constructed the maps between \ref{eq:univ-0} and \ref{eq:univ-1}. It
|
||||||
|
|
|
@ -1,7 +1,7 @@
|
||||||
\chapter{Introduction}
|
\chapter{Introduction}
|
||||||
Functional extensionality and univalence is not expressible in
|
Functional extensionality and univalence is not expressible in
|
||||||
\nomen{Intensional Martin Löf Type Theory} (ITT). This poses a severe limitation
|
\nomen{Intensional Martin Löf Type Theory} (ITT). This poses a severe limitation
|
||||||
on both 1) what is \emph{provable} and 2) the \emph{reusability} of proofs.
|
on both i. what is \emph{provable} and ii. the \emph{reusability} of proofs.
|
||||||
Recent developments have, however, resulted in \nomen{Cubical Type Theory} (CTT)
|
Recent developments have, however, resulted in \nomen{Cubical Type Theory} (CTT)
|
||||||
which permits a constructive proof of these two important notions.
|
which permits a constructive proof of these two important notions.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
@ -19,9 +19,13 @@ limitations inherent in ITT and -- by extension -- Agda.
|
||||||
Consider the functions:
|
Consider the functions:
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
\begin{multicols}{2}
|
\begin{multicols}{2}
|
||||||
$f \defeq (n : \bN) \mapsto (0 + n : \bN)$
|
\noindent
|
||||||
|
\begin{equation*}
|
||||||
$g \defeq (n : \bN) \mapsto (n + 0 : \bN)$
|
f \defeq (n : \bN) \mapsto (0 + n : \bN)
|
||||||
|
\end{equation*}
|
||||||
|
\begin{equation*}
|
||||||
|
g \defeq (n : \bN) \mapsto (n + 0 : \bN)
|
||||||
|
\end{equation*}
|
||||||
\end{multicols}
|
\end{multicols}
|
||||||
%
|
%
|
||||||
$n + 0$ is \nomen{definitionally} equal to $n$, which we write as $n + 0 = n$.
|
$n + 0$ is \nomen{definitionally} equal to $n$, which we write as $n + 0 = n$.
|
||||||
|
@ -160,7 +164,7 @@ Another approach is to use the \emph{setoid interpretation} of type theory
|
||||||
equivalence relation $\sim \tp X \to X \to \MCU$ on that type. Under the setoid
|
equivalence relation $\sim \tp X \to X \to \MCU$ on that type. Under the setoid
|
||||||
interpretation the equivalence relation serve as a sort of ``local''
|
interpretation the equivalence relation serve as a sort of ``local''
|
||||||
propositional equality. This approach has other drawbacks; it does not satisfy
|
propositional equality. This approach has other drawbacks; it does not satisfy
|
||||||
all propositional equalites of type theory (\TODO{Citation needed}, is
|
all propositional equalites of type theory (\TODO{Citation needed}), is
|
||||||
cumbersome to work with in practice (\cite[p. 4]{huber-2016}) and makes
|
cumbersome to work with in practice (\cite[p. 4]{huber-2016}) and makes
|
||||||
equational proofs less reusable since equational proofs $a \sim_{X} b$ are
|
equational proofs less reusable since equational proofs $a \sim_{X} b$ are
|
||||||
inherently `local' to the extensional set $(X , \sim)$.
|
inherently `local' to the extensional set $(X , \sim)$.
|
||||||
|
@ -192,9 +196,9 @@ Name & Agda & Notation \\
|
||||||
Function, morphism, map & \texttt{A → B} & $A → B$ \\
|
Function, morphism, map & \texttt{A → B} & $A → B$ \\
|
||||||
Dependent- ditto & \texttt{(a : A) → B} & $∏_{a \tp A} → B$ \\
|
Dependent- ditto & \texttt{(a : A) → B} & $∏_{a \tp A} → B$ \\
|
||||||
\nomen{Arrow} & \texttt{Arrow A B} & $\Arrow\ A\ B$ \\
|
\nomen{Arrow} & \texttt{Arrow A B} & $\Arrow\ A\ B$ \\
|
||||||
\nomen{Object} & \texttt{C.Object} & $̱ℂ.Object$
|
\nomen{Object} & \texttt{C.Object} & $̱ℂ.Object$ \\
|
||||||
Definition & \texttt{=} & $̱\defeq$
|
Definition & \texttt{=} & $̱\defeq$ \\
|
||||||
Judgmental equality & \null & $̱=$
|
Judgmental equality & \null & $̱=$ \\
|
||||||
Propositional equality & \null & $̱\equiv$
|
Propositional equality & \null & $̱\equiv$
|
||||||
\end{tabular}
|
\end{tabular}
|
||||||
\end{center}
|
\end{center}
|
||||||
|
|
Loading…
Reference in a new issue