2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
This implementation formalizes the following concepts:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{itemize}
|
|
|
|
|
\item Core categorical concepts
|
|
|
|
|
\subitem Categories
|
|
|
|
|
\subitem Functors
|
|
|
|
|
\subitem Products
|
|
|
|
|
\subitem Exponentials
|
|
|
|
|
\subitem Cartesian closed categories
|
|
|
|
|
\subitem Natural transformations
|
|
|
|
|
\subitem Yoneda embedding
|
|
|
|
|
\subitem Monads
|
|
|
|
|
\subsubitem Monoidal monads
|
|
|
|
|
\subsubitem Kleisli monads
|
|
|
|
|
\subsubitem Voevodsky's construction
|
|
|
|
|
\item Category of \ldots
|
|
|
|
|
\subitem Homotopy sets
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\subitem Categories -- only data-part
|
|
|
|
|
\subitem Relations -- only data-part
|
|
|
|
|
\subitem Functors -- only as a precategory
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\subitem Free category
|
|
|
|
|
\end{itemize}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
Since it is useful to distinguish between types with more or less (homotopical)
|
|
|
|
|
structure I have followed the following design-principle: I have split concepts
|
|
|
|
|
up into things that represent ``data'' and ``laws'' about this data. The idea is
|
|
|
|
|
that we can provide a proof that the laws are mere propositions. As an example a
|
|
|
|
|
category is defined to have two members: `raw` which is a collection of the data
|
|
|
|
|
and `isCategory` which asserts some laws about that data.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
This allows me to reason about things in a more mathematical way, where one can
|
|
|
|
|
reason about two categories by simply focusing on the data. This is acheived by
|
|
|
|
|
creating a function embodying the ``equality principle'' for a given type.
|
|
|
|
|
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\section{Categories}
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
The data for a category consist of objects, morphisms (or arrows as I will refer
|
|
|
|
|
to them henceforth), the identity arrow and composition of arrows.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Another record encapsulates some laws about this data: associativity of
|
|
|
|
|
composition, identity law for the identity morphism. These are standard
|
|
|
|
|
requirements for being a category as can be found in standard mathematical
|
|
|
|
|
expositions on the topic. We, however, impose one further requirement on what it
|
|
|
|
|
means to be a category, namely that the type of arrows form a set. We could
|
|
|
|
|
relax this requirement, this would give us the notion of higher categorier
|
|
|
|
|
(\cite[p. 307]{hott-2013}). For the purpose of this project, however, this
|
|
|
|
|
report will restrict itself to 1-categories.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Raw categories satisfying these properties are called a pre-categories.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
As a further requirement to be a proper category we require it to be univalent.
|
|
|
|
|
This requirement is quite similiar to univalence for types, but we let
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
isomorphism on objects play the role of equivalence on types. The univalence
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
criterion is:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\isEquiv\ (A \equiv B)\ (A \approxeq B)\ \idToIso
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
Here $\approxeq$ denotes isomorphism on objects (whereas $\cong$ denotes
|
|
|
|
|
isomorphism of types).
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Note that this is not the same as:
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
(A \equiv B) \simeq (A \approxeq B)
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
The two types are logically equivalent, however. One can construct the latter
|
|
|
|
|
from the formerr simply by ``forgetting'' that $\idToIso$ plays the role
|
|
|
|
|
of the equivalence. The other direction is more involved.
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
With all this in place it is now possible to prove that all the laws are indeed
|
|
|
|
|
mere propositions. Most of the proofs simply use the fact that the type of
|
|
|
|
|
arrows are sets. This is because most of the laws are a collection of equations
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
between arrows in the category. And since such a proof does not have any content
|
|
|
|
|
exactly because the type of arrows form a set, two witnesses must be the same.
|
|
|
|
|
All the proofs are really quite mechanical. Lets have a look at one of them: The
|
|
|
|
|
identity law states that:
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\prod_{A\ B \tp \Object} \prod_{f \tp A \to B} \id \comp f \equiv f \x f \comp \id \equiv f
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
There are multiple ways to prove this. Perhaps one of the more intuitive proofs
|
|
|
|
|
is by way of the following `combinators':
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
\mathit{propPi} \tp \left(\prod_{a \tp A} \isProp\ (P\ a)\right) \to \isProp\ \left(\prod_{a \tp A} P\ a\right)
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
I.e.; pi-types preserve propositionality when the co-domain is always a
|
|
|
|
|
proposition.
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\mathit{propSig} \tp \isProp\ A \to \left(\prod_{a \tp A} \isProp\ (P\ a)\right) \to \isProp\ \left(\sum_{a \tp A} P\ a\right)
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
I.e.; sigma-types preserve propositionality whenever it's first component is a
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
proposition, and it's second component is a proposition for all points of in the
|
|
|
|
|
left type.
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
So the proof goes like this: We `eliminate' the 3 function abstractions by
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
applying $\propPi$ three times. So our proof obligation becomes:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
\isProp \left( \id \comp f \equiv f \x f \comp \id \equiv f \right)
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
then we eliminate the (non-dependent) sigma-type by applying $\propSig$ giving
|
|
|
|
|
us the two obligations: $\isProp\ (\id \comp f \equiv f)$ and $\isProp\ (f \comp
|
|
|
|
|
\id \equiv f)$ which follows from the type of arrows being a set.
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
This example illustrates nicely how we can use these combinators to reason about
|
|
|
|
|
`canonical' types like $\sum$ and $\prod$. Similiar combinators can be defined
|
|
|
|
|
at the other homotopic levels. These combinators are however not applicable in
|
|
|
|
|
situations where we want to reason about other types - e.g. types we've defined
|
|
|
|
|
ourselves. For instance, after we've proven that all the projections of
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
pre-categories are propositions, then we would like to bundle this up to show
|
|
|
|
|
that the type of pre-categories is also a proposition. Since pre-categories are
|
|
|
|
|
not formulated with a chain of sigma-types we wont have any combinators
|
|
|
|
|
available to help us here. In stead we'll have to use the path-type directly.
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
What we want to prove is:
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
\isProp\ \IsPreCategory
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
Which is judgmentally the same as
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
\prod_{a\ b \tp \IsPreCategory} a \equiv b
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
So let $a\ b \tp \IsPreCategory$ be given. To prove the equality $a \equiv b$ is
|
|
|
|
|
to give a continuous path from the index-type into path-space - in this case
|
|
|
|
|
$\IsPreCategory$. This path must satisfy being being judgmentally the same as
|
|
|
|
|
$a$ at the left endpoint and $b$ at the right endpoint. I.e. a function $I \to
|
|
|
|
|
\IsPreCategory$. We know we can form a continuous path between all projections
|
|
|
|
|
of $a$ and $b$, this follows from the type of all the projections being mere
|
|
|
|
|
propositions. For instance, the path between $\isIdentity_a$ and $\isIdentity_b$
|
|
|
|
|
is simply formed by:
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
\propIsIdentity\ \isIdentity_a\ \isIdentity_b \tp \isIdentity_a \equiv \isIdentity_b
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
So to give the continuous function $I \to \IsPreCategory$ that is our goal we
|
|
|
|
|
introduce $i \tp I$ and proceed by constructing an element of $\IsPreCategory$
|
|
|
|
|
by using that all the projections are propositions to generate paths between all
|
|
|
|
|
projections. Once we have such a path e.g. $p : \isIdentity_a \equiv
|
|
|
|
|
\isIdentity_b$ we can elimiate it with $i$ and thus obtaining $p\ i \tp
|
|
|
|
|
\isIdentity_{p\ i}$ and this element satisfies exactly that it corresponds to
|
|
|
|
|
the corresponding projections at either endpoint. Thus the element we construct
|
|
|
|
|
at $i$ becomes:
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
& \{\ \mathit{propIsAssociative}\ \mathit{isAssociative}_x\
|
|
|
|
|
\mathit{isAssociative}_y\ i \\
|
|
|
|
|
& ,\ \mathit{propIsIdentity}\ \mathit{isIdentity}_x\
|
|
|
|
|
\mathit{isIdentity}_y\ i \\
|
|
|
|
|
& ,\ \mathit{propArrowsAreSets}\ \mathit{arrowsAreSets}_x\
|
|
|
|
|
\mathit{arrowsAreSets}_y\ i \\
|
|
|
|
|
& \}
|
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
I've found that this to be a general pattern when proving things in homotopy
|
|
|
|
|
type theory, namely that you have to wrap and unwrap equalities at different
|
|
|
|
|
levels. It is worth noting that proving this theorem with the regular inductive
|
|
|
|
|
equality type would already not be possible, since we at least need
|
|
|
|
|
extensionality (the projections are all $\prod$-types). Assuming we had
|
|
|
|
|
functional extensionality available to us as an axiom, we would use functional
|
|
|
|
|
extensionality (in reverse?) to retreive the equalities in $a$ and $b$,
|
|
|
|
|
pattern-match on them to see that they are both $\mathit{refl}$ and then close
|
|
|
|
|
the proof with $\mathit{refl}$. Of course this theorem is not so interesting in
|
|
|
|
|
the setting of ITT since we know a priori that equality proofs are unique.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
The situation is a bit more complicated when we have a dependent type. For
|
|
|
|
|
instance, when we want to show that $\IsCategory$ is a mere proposition.
|
|
|
|
|
$\IsCategory$ is a record with two fields, a witness to being a pre-category and
|
|
|
|
|
the univalence condition. Recall that the univalence condition is indexed by the
|
|
|
|
|
identity-proof. So if we follow the same recipe as above, let $a\ b \tp
|
|
|
|
|
\IsCategory$, to show them equal, we now need to give two paths. One homogenous:
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
p_{\isPreCategory} \tp \isPreCategory_a \equiv \isPreCategory_b
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
and one heterogeneous:
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-04-24 12:11:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\Path\ (\lambda\; i \mto Univalent_{p\ i})\ \isPreCategory_a\ \isPreCategory_b
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
Which depends on the choice of $p_{\isPreCategory}$. The first of these we can
|
|
|
|
|
provide since, as we have shown, $\IsPreCategory$ is a proposition. However,
|
|
|
|
|
even though $\Univalent$ is also a proposition, we cannot use this directly to
|
|
|
|
|
show the latter. This is becasue $\isProp$ talks about non-dependent paths. To
|
|
|
|
|
`promote' this to a dependent path we can use another useful combinator;
|
|
|
|
|
$\lemPropF$. Given a type $A \tp \MCU$ and a type family on $A$; $B : A \to
|
|
|
|
|
\MCU$. Let $P$ be a proposition indexed by an element of $A$ and say we have a
|
|
|
|
|
path between some two elements in $A$; $p : a_0 \equiv a_1$ then we can built a
|
|
|
|
|
heterogeneous path between any two $b$'s at the endpoints:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-04-24 12:11:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\Path\ (\lambda\; i \mto B\ (p\ i))\ b0\ b1
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
where $b_0 \tp B a_0$ and $b_1 \tp B\ a_1$. This is quite a mouthful, but the
|
|
|
|
|
example at present should serve as an illustration. In this case $A =
|
|
|
|
|
\mathit{IsIdentity}\ \mathit{identity}$ and $B = \mathit{Univalent}$ we've shown
|
|
|
|
|
that being a category is a proposition, a result that holds for any choice of
|
|
|
|
|
identity proof. Finally we must provide a proof that the identity proofs at $a$
|
|
|
|
|
and $b$ are indeed the same, this we can extract from $p_{\isPreCategory}$ by
|
|
|
|
|
applying using congruence of paths: $\congruence\ \mathit{isIdentity}\
|
|
|
|
|
p_{\isPreCategory}$
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
When we have a proper category we can make precise the notion of ``identifying
|
2018-04-24 12:11:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
isomorphic types'' \TODO{cite awodey here}. That is, we can construct the
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
function:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\isoToId \tp (A \approxeq B) \to (A \equiv B)
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
One application of this, and a perhaps somewhat surprising result, is that
|
|
|
|
|
terminal objects are propositional. Intuitively; they do not have any
|
|
|
|
|
interesting structure. The proof of this follows from the usual observation that
|
|
|
|
|
any two terminal objects are isomorphic. The proof is omitted here, but the
|
2018-04-24 12:11:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
curious reader can check the implementation for the details. \TODO{The proof is
|
|
|
|
|
a bit fun, should I include it?}
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\section{Equivalences}
|
2018-04-24 12:11:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\label{sec:equiv}
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
The usual notion of a function $f : A \to B$ having an inverses is:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
\sum_{g : B \to A} f \comp g \equiv \identity_{B} \x g \comp f \equiv \identity_{A}
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
This is defined in \cite[p. 129]{hott-2013} and is referred to as the a
|
|
|
|
|
quasi-inverse. At the same place \cite{hott-2013} gives an ``interface'' for
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
what an equivalence $\isEquiv : (A \to B) \to \MCU$ must supply:
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{itemize}
|
|
|
|
|
\item
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$\qinv\ f \to \isEquiv\ f$
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\item
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$\isEquiv\ f \to \qinv\ f$
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\item
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$\isEquiv\ f$ is a proposition
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\end{itemize}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
Having such an interface gives us both 1) a way to think rather abstractly about
|
|
|
|
|
how to work with equivalences and 2) to use ad-hoc definitions of equivalences.
|
2018-04-24 12:11:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
The specific instantiation of $\isEquiv$ as defined in \cite{cubical-agda} is:
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
isEquiv\ f \defeq \prod_{b : B} \isContr\ (\fiber\ f\ b)
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
where
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
\fiber\ f\ b \defeq \sum_{a \tp A} b \equiv f\ a
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
I give it's definition here mainly for completeness, because as I stated we can
|
|
|
|
|
move away from this specific instantiation and think about it more abstractly
|
|
|
|
|
once we have shown that this definition actually works as an equivalence.
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
The first function from the list of requirements we will call
|
|
|
|
|
$\mathit{fromIsomorphism}$, this is known as $\mathit{gradLemma}$ in
|
2018-04-24 12:11:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\cite{cubical-agda} the second one we will refer to as $\mathit{toIsmorphism}$. It's
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
implementation can be found in the sources. Likewise the proof that this
|
|
|
|
|
equivalence is propositional can be found in my implementation.
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
We say that two types $A\;B \tp \Type$ are equivalent exactly if there exists an
|
|
|
|
|
equivalence between them:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
A \simeq B \defeq \sum_{f \tp A \to B} \isEquiv\ f
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
Note that the term equivalence here is overloaded referring both to the map $f
|
|
|
|
|
\tp A \to B$ and the type $A \simeq B$. I will use these conflated terms when it
|
|
|
|
|
it is clear from the context what is being referred to.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Just like we could promote a quasi-inverse to an equivalence we can promote an
|
|
|
|
|
isomorphism to an equivalence:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
\mathit{fromIsomorphism} \tp A \cong B \to A \simeq B
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
and vice-versa:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
\mathit{toIsomorphism} \tp A \simeq B \to A \cong B
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
The notion of an isomorphism is similarly conflated as isomorphism can refer to
|
|
|
|
|
the type $A \cong B$ as well as the the map $A \to B$ that witness this.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Both $\cong$ and $\simeq$ form equivalence relations.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\section{Univalence}
|
|
|
|
|
\label{univalence}
|
|
|
|
|
As noted in the introduction the univalence for types $A\; B \tp \Type$ states
|
|
|
|
|
that:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
\mathit{Univalence} \defeq (A \equiv B) \simeq (A \simeq B)
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
As mentioned the univalence criterion for some category $\bC$ says that for all
|
|
|
|
|
\emph{objects} $A\;B$ we must have:
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
\isEquiv\ (A \equiv B)\ (A \approxeq B)\ \idToIso
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
And I mentioned that this was logically equivalent to
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
(A \equiv B) \simeq (A \approxeq B)
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
Given that we saw in the previous section that we can construct an equivalence
|
|
|
|
|
from an isomorphism it suffices to demonstrate:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
(A \equiv B) \cong (A \approxeq B)
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
That is, we must demonstrate that there is an isomorphism (on types) between
|
|
|
|
|
equalities and isomorphisms (on arrows). It's worthwhile to dwell on this for a
|
|
|
|
|
few seconds. This type looks very similar to univalence for types and is
|
|
|
|
|
therefore perhaps a bit more intuitive to grasp the implications of. Of course
|
|
|
|
|
univalence for types (which is a proposition -- i.e. provable) does not imply
|
|
|
|
|
univalence in any category since morphisms in a category are not regular maps --
|
|
|
|
|
in stead they can be thought of as a generalization hereof; i.e. arrows. The
|
|
|
|
|
univalence criterion therefore is simply a way of restricting arrows to behave
|
|
|
|
|
similarly to maps.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
I will now mention a few helpful thoerems that follow from univalence that will
|
|
|
|
|
become useful later.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Obviously univalence gives us an isomorphism $A \equiv B \to A \approxeq B$. I
|
|
|
|
|
will name these for convenience:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
\idToIso \tp A \equiv B \to A \approxeq B
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
\isoToId \tp A \approxeq B \to A \equiv B
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-04-24 12:11:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
The next few theorems are variations on theorem 9.1.9 from \cite{hott-2013}. Let
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
an isomorphism $A \approxeq B$ in some category $\bC$ be given. Name the
|
|
|
|
|
isomorphism $\iota \tp A \to B$ and its inverse $\widetilde{\iota} \tp B \to A$.
|
|
|
|
|
Since $\bC$ is a category (and therefore univalent) the isomorphism induces a
|
|
|
|
|
path $p \tp A \equiv B$. From this equality we can get two further paths:
|
|
|
|
|
$p_{\mathit{dom}} \tp \mathit{Arrow}\ A\ X \equiv \mathit{Arrow}\ A'\ X$ and
|
|
|
|
|
$p_{\mathit{cod}} \tp \mathit{Arrow}\ X\ A \equiv \mathit{Arrow}\ X\ A'$. We
|
|
|
|
|
then have the following two theorems:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
\mathit{coeDom} \tp \prod_{f \tp A \to X} \mathit{coe}\ p_{\mathit{dom}}\ f \equiv f \lll \widetilde{\iota}
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
\mathit{coeCod} \tp \prod_{f \tp A \to X} \mathit{coe}\ p_{\mathit{cod}}\ f \equiv \iota \lll f
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
I will give the proof of the first theorem here, the second one is analagous.
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
\mathit{coe}\ p_{\mathit{dom}}\ f
|
|
|
|
|
& \equiv f \lll \mathit{obverse}_{\mathit{idToIso}\ p} && \text{lemma} \\
|
|
|
|
|
& \equiv f \lll \widetilde{\iota}
|
|
|
|
|
&& \text{$\mathit{idToIso}$ and $\mathit{isoToId}$ are inverses}\\
|
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
In the second step we use the fact that $p$ is constructed from the isomorphism
|
|
|
|
|
$\iota$ -- $\mathit{obverse}$ denotes the map $B \to A$ induced by the
|
|
|
|
|
isomorphism $\mathit{idToIso}\ p \tp A \cong B$. The helper-lemma is similar to
|
|
|
|
|
what we're trying to prove but talks about paths rather than isomorphisms:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
\prod_{f \tp \mathit{Arrow}\ A\ B} \prod_{p \tp A \equiv A'} \mathit{coe}\ p^*\ f \equiv f \lll \mathit{obverse}_{\mathit{idToIso}\ p}
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
Note that the asterisk in $p^*$ denotes the path $\mathit{Arrow}\ A\ B \equiv
|
|
|
|
|
\mathit{Arrow}\ A'\ B$ induced by $p$. To prove this statement I let $f$ and $p$
|
|
|
|
|
be given and then invoke based-path-induction. The induction will be based at $A
|
|
|
|
|
\tp \mathit{Object}$, so let $\widetilde{A} \tp \Object$ and $\widetilde{p} \tp
|
|
|
|
|
A \equiv \widetilde{A}$ be given. The family that we perform induction over will
|
|
|
|
|
be:
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\mathit{coe}\ {\widetilde{p}}^*\ f \equiv f \lll \mathit{obverse}_{\mathit{idToIso}\ \widetilde{p}}
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
The base-case therefore becomes:
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
\mathit{coe}\ {\widetilde{\refl}}^*\ f
|
|
|
|
|
& \equiv f \\
|
|
|
|
|
& \equiv f \lll \mathit{identity} \\
|
|
|
|
|
& \equiv f \lll \mathit{obverse}_{\mathit{idToIso}\ \widetilde{\refl}}
|
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
The first step follows because reflixivity is a neutral element for coercions.
|
|
|
|
|
The second step is the identity law in the category. The last step has to do
|
|
|
|
|
with the fact that $\mathit{idToIso}$ is constructed by substituting according
|
|
|
|
|
to the supplied path and since reflexivity is also the neutral element for
|
|
|
|
|
substuitutions we arrive at the desired expression. To close the
|
|
|
|
|
based-path-induction we must supply the value at the other end and the
|
|
|
|
|
connecting path, but in this case this is simply $A' \tp \Object$ and $p \tp A
|
|
|
|
|
\equiv A'$ which we have.
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\section{Categories}
|
|
|
|
|
\subsection{Opposite category}
|
|
|
|
|
\label{op-cat}
|
|
|
|
|
The first category I'll present is a pure construction on categories. Given some
|
|
|
|
|
category we can construct it's dual, called the opposite category. Starting with
|
|
|
|
|
a simple example allows us to focus on how we work with equivalences and
|
|
|
|
|
univalence in a very simple category where the structure of the category is
|
|
|
|
|
rather simple.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Let $\bC$ be some category, we then define the opposite category
|
2018-04-24 12:11:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$\bC^{\mathit{Op}}$. It has the same objects, but the type of arrows are flipped,
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
that is to say an arrow from $A$ to $B$ in the opposite category corresponds to
|
|
|
|
|
an arrow from $B$ to $A$ in the underlying category. The identity arrow is the
|
|
|
|
|
same as the one in the underlying category (they have the same type). Function
|
|
|
|
|
composition will be reverse function composition from the underlying category.
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
Showing that this forms a pre-category is rather straightforward. I'll state the
|
|
|
|
|
laws in terms of the underlying category $\bC$:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
h \rrr (g \rrr f) \equiv h \rrr g \rrr f
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
Since $\rrr$ is reverse function composition this is just the symmetric version
|
|
|
|
|
of associativity.
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-04-24 12:11:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\mathit{identity} \rrr f \equiv f \x f \rrr identity \equiv f
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
This is just the swapped version of identity.
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
Finally, that the arrows form sets just follows by flipping the order of the
|
|
|
|
|
arguments. Or in other words since $\Hom_{A\ B}$ is a set for all $A\ B \tp
|
|
|
|
|
\Object$ then so is $\Hom_{B\ A}$.
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
Now, to show that this category is univalent is not as straight-forward. Lucliy
|
2018-04-24 12:11:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
section \ref{sec:equiv} gave us some tools to work with equivalences. We saw that we
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
can prove this category univalent by giving an inverse to
|
|
|
|
|
$\idToIso_{\mathit{Op}} \tp (A \equiv B) \to (A \approxeq_{\mathit{Op}} B)$.
|
|
|
|
|
From the original category we have that $\idToIso \tp (A \equiv B) \to (A \cong
|
|
|
|
|
B)$ is an isomorphism. Let us denote it's inverse with $\eta \tp (A \approxeq B)
|
|
|
|
|
\to (A \equiv B)$. If we squint we can see what we need is a way to go between
|
|
|
|
|
$\approxeq_{\mathit{Op}}$ and $\approxeq$, well, an inhabitant of $A \approxeq
|
|
|
|
|
B$ is simply an arrow $f \tp \mathit{Arrow}\ A\ B$ and it's inverse $g \tp
|
|
|
|
|
\mathit{Arrow}\ B\ A$. In the opposite category $g$ will play the role of the
|
|
|
|
|
isomorphism and $f$ will be the inverse. Similarly we can go in the opposite
|
|
|
|
|
direction. I name these maps $\mathit{shuffle} \tp (A \approxeq B) \to (A
|
|
|
|
|
\approxeq_{\bC} B)$ and $\mathit{shuffle}^{-1} : (A \approxeq_{\bC} B) \to (A
|
|
|
|
|
\approxeq B)$ respectively.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
As the inverse of $\idToIso_{\mathit{Op}}$ I will pick $\zeta \defeq \eta \comp
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\mathit{shuffle}$. The proof that they are inverses go as follows:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
\zeta \comp \idToIso & \equiv
|
|
|
|
|
\eta \comp \shuffle \comp \idToIso
|
|
|
|
|
&& \text{by definition} \\
|
|
|
|
|
%% ≡⟨ cong (λ φ → φ x) (cong (λ φ → η ⊙ shuffle ⊙ φ) (funExt lem)) ⟩ \\
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
& \equiv
|
|
|
|
|
\eta \comp \shuffle \comp \inv{\shuffle} \comp \idToIso
|
|
|
|
|
&& \text{lemma} \\
|
|
|
|
|
%% ≡⟨⟩ \\
|
|
|
|
|
& \equiv
|
|
|
|
|
\eta \comp \idToIso_{\bC}
|
|
|
|
|
&& \text{$\shuffle$ is an isomorphism} \\
|
|
|
|
|
%% ≡⟨ (λ i → verso-recto i x) ⟩ \\
|
|
|
|
|
& \equiv
|
|
|
|
|
\identity
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
&& \text{$\eta$ is an ismorphism}
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
The other direction is analogous.
|
|
|
|
|
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
The lemma used in this proof states that $\idToIso \equiv \inv{\shuffle} \comp
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\idToIso_{\bC}$ it's a rather straight-forward proof since being-an-inverse-of
|
|
|
|
|
is a proposition.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
So, in conclusion, we've shown that the opposite category is indeed a category.
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
This finished the proof that the opposite category is in fact a category. Now,
|
|
|
|
|
to prove that that opposite-of is an involution we must show:
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-04-24 12:11:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\prod_{\bC \tp \mathit{Category}} \left(\bC^{\mathit{Op}}\right)^{\mathit{Op}} \equiv \bC
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
As we've seen the laws in $\left(\bC^{\mathit{Op}}\right)^{\mathit{Op}}$ get
|
|
|
|
|
quite involved.\footnote{We haven't even seen the full story because we've used
|
|
|
|
|
this `interface' for equivalences.} Luckily since being-a-category is a mere
|
|
|
|
|
proposition, we need not concern ourselves with this bit when proving the above.
|
|
|
|
|
We can use the equality principle for categories that lets us prove an equality
|
|
|
|
|
just by giving an equality on the data-part. So, given a category $\bC$ all we
|
|
|
|
|
must provide is the following proof:
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\mathit{raw}\ \left(\bC^{\mathit{Op}}\right)^{\mathit{Op}} \equiv \mathit{raw}\ \bC
|
2018-04-05 18:41:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
And these are judgmentally the same. I remind the reader that the left-hand side
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
is constructed by flipping the arrows, which judgmentally is an involution.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\subsection{Category of sets}
|
|
|
|
|
The category of sets has as objects, not types, but only those types that are
|
|
|
|
|
homotopic sets. This is encapsulated in Agda with the following type:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$\Set_\ell \defeq \sum_{A \tp \MCU_\ell} \isSet\ A$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
The more straight-forward notion of a category where the objects are types is
|
|
|
|
|
not a valid (1-)category. Since in cubical Agda types can have higher homotopic
|
|
|
|
|
structure.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Univalence does not follow immediately from univalence for types:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$(A \equiv B) \simeq (A \simeq B)$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
Because here $A\ B \tp \Type$ whereas the objects in this category have the type
|
|
|
|
|
$\Set$ so we cannot form the type $\mathit{hA} \simeq \mathit{hB}$ for objects
|
|
|
|
|
$\mathit{hA}\;\mathit{hB} \tp \Set$. In stead I show that this category
|
|
|
|
|
satisfies:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
(\mathit{hA} \equiv \mathit{hB}) \simeq (\mathit{hA} \approxeq \mathit{hB})
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
Which, as we saw in section \ref{univalence}, is sufficient to show that the
|
|
|
|
|
category is univalent. The way that I have shown this is with a three-step
|
2018-04-24 12:11:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
process. For objects $(A, s_A)\; (B, s_B) \tp \Set$ I show the following chain
|
|
|
|
|
of equivalences:
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
2018-04-24 12:11:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
((A, s_A) \equiv (B, s_B))
|
|
|
|
|
& \simeq (A \equiv B) && \ref{eq:equivPropSig} \\
|
|
|
|
|
& \simeq (A \simeq B) && \text{Univalence} \\
|
|
|
|
|
& \simeq ((A, s_A) \approxeq (B, s_B)) && \text{\ref{eq:equivSig} and \ref{eq:equivIso}}
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
And since $\simeq$ is an equivalence relation we can chain these equivalences
|
|
|
|
|
together. Step one will be proven with the following lemma:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-04-24 12:11:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\begin{align}
|
|
|
|
|
\label{eq:equivPropSig}
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\left(\prod_{a \tp A} \isProp (P\ a)\right) \to \prod_{x\;y \tp \sum_{a \tp A} P\ a} (x \equiv y) \simeq (\fst\ x \equiv \fst\ y)
|
2018-04-24 12:11:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\end{align}
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
The lemma states that for pairs whose second component are mere propositions
|
|
|
|
|
equiality is equivalent to equality of the first components. In this case the
|
|
|
|
|
type-family $P$ is $\isSet$ which itself is a proposition for any type $A \tp
|
|
|
|
|
\Type$. Step two is univalence. Step three will be proven with the following
|
|
|
|
|
lemma:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-04-24 12:11:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\begin{align}
|
|
|
|
|
\label{eq:equivSig}
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\prod_{a \tp A} \left( P\ a \simeq Q\ a \right) \to \sum_{a \tp A} P\ a \simeq \sum_{a \tp A} Q\ a
|
2018-04-24 12:11:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\end{align}
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
Which says that if two type-families are equivalent at all points, then pairs
|
|
|
|
|
with identitical first components and these families as second components will
|
|
|
|
|
also be equivalent. For our purposes $P \defeq \isEquiv\ A\ B$ and $Q \defeq
|
|
|
|
|
\mathit{Isomorphism}$. So we must finally prove:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-04-24 12:11:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\begin{align}
|
|
|
|
|
\label{eq:equivIso}
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\prod_{f \tp A \to B} \left( \isEquiv\ A\ B\ f \simeq \mathit{Isomorphism}\ f \right)
|
2018-04-24 12:11:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\end{align}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
First, lets proove \ref{eq:equivPropSig}: Let $propP \tp \prod_{a \tp A} \isProp (P\ a)$ and $x\;y \tp \sum_{a \tp A} P\ a$ be given. Because
|
|
|
|
|
of $\mathit{fromIsomorphism}$ it suffices to give an isomorphism between
|
|
|
|
|
$x \equiv y$ and $\fst\ x \equiv \fst\ y$:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
f & \defeq \congruence\ \fst \tp x \equiv y \to \fst\ x \equiv \fst\ y \\
|
|
|
|
|
g & \defeq \mathit{lemSig}\ \mathit{propP}\ x\ y \tp \fst\ x \equiv \fst\ y \to x \equiv y
|
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\TODO{Is it confusing that I use point-free style here?}
|
|
|
|
|
Here $\mathit{lemSig}$ is a lemma that says that if the second component of a
|
|
|
|
|
pair is a proposition, it suffices to give a path between it's first components
|
|
|
|
|
to construct an equality of the two pairs:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
\mathit{lemSig} \tp \left( \prod_{x \tp A} \isProp\ (B\ x) \right) \to
|
|
|
|
|
\prod_{u\; v \tp \sum_{a \tp A} B\ a}
|
|
|
|
|
\left( \fst\ u \equiv \fst\ v \right) \to u \equiv v
|
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
The proof that these are indeed inverses has been omitted. \TODO{Do I really
|
|
|
|
|
want to ommit it?}\QED
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
2018-04-24 12:11:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
Now to prove \ref{eq:equivSig}: Let $e \tp \prod_{a \tp A} \left( P\ a \simeq
|
|
|
|
|
Q\ a \right)$ be given. To prove the equivalence, it suffices to give an
|
|
|
|
|
isomorphism between $\sum_{a \tp A} P\ a$ and $\sum_{a \tp A} Q\ a$, but since
|
|
|
|
|
they have identical first components it suffices to give an isomorphism between
|
|
|
|
|
$P\ a$ and $Q\ a$ for all $a \tp A$. This is exactly what we can get from
|
|
|
|
|
the equivalence $e$.\QED
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
2018-04-24 12:11:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
Lastly we prove \ref{eq:equivIso}. Let $f \tp A \to B$ be given. For the maps we
|
|
|
|
|
choose:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
\mathit{toIso}
|
|
|
|
|
& \tp \isEquiv\ f \to \mathit{Isomorphism}\ f \\
|
|
|
|
|
\mathit{fromIso}
|
|
|
|
|
& \tp \mathit{Isomorphism}\ f \to \isEquiv\ f
|
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
As mentioned in section \ref{sec:equiv}. These maps are not in general inverses
|
|
|
|
|
of each other. In stead, we will use the fact that $A$ and $B$ are sets. The first thing we must prove is:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
\mathit{fromIso} \comp \mathit{toIso} \equiv \identity_{\isEquiv\ f}
|
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
For this we can use the fact that being-an-equivalence is a mere proposition.
|
|
|
|
|
For the other direction:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
\mathit{toIso} \comp \mathit{fromIso} \equiv \identity_{\mathit{Isomorphism}\ f}
|
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
We will show that $\mathit{Isomorphism}\ f$ is also a mere proposition. To this
|
|
|
|
|
end, let $X\;Y \tp \mathit{Isomorphism}\ f$ be given. Name the maps $x\;y \tp B
|
|
|
|
|
\to A$ respectively. Now, the proof that $X$ and $Y$ are the same is a pair of
|
|
|
|
|
paths: $p \tp x \equiv y$ and $\Path\ (\lambda\; i \mto
|
|
|
|
|
\mathit{AreInverses}\ f\ (p\ i))\ \mathcal{X}\ \mathcal{Y}$ where $\mathcal{X}$
|
|
|
|
|
and $\mathcal{Y}$ denotes the witnesses that $x$ (respectively $y$) is an
|
|
|
|
|
inverse to $f$. $p$ is inhabited by:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
x
|
|
|
|
|
& \equiv x \comp \identity \\
|
|
|
|
|
& \equiv x \comp (f \comp y)
|
|
|
|
|
&& \text{$y$ is an inverse to $f$} \\
|
|
|
|
|
& \equiv (x \comp f) \comp y \\
|
|
|
|
|
& \equiv \identity \comp y
|
|
|
|
|
&& \text{$x$ is an inverse to $f$} \\
|
|
|
|
|
& \equiv y
|
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
For the other (dependent) path we can prove that being-an-inverse-of is a
|
|
|
|
|
proposition and then use $\lemPropF$. So we prove the generalization:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
\prod_{g : B \to A} \isProp\ (\mathit{AreInverses}\ f\ g)
|
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
But $\mathit{AreInverses}\ f\ g$ is a pair of equations on arrows, so we use
|
|
|
|
|
$\propSig$ and the fact that both $A$ and $B$ are sets to close this proof.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\subsection{Category of categories}
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
Note that this category does in fact not exist. In stead I provide the
|
|
|
|
|
definition of the ``raw'' category as well as some of the laws.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Furthermore I provide some helpful lemmas about this raw category. For instance
|
|
|
|
|
I have shown what would be the exponential object in such a category.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
These lemmas can be used to provide the actual exponential object in a context
|
|
|
|
|
where we have a witness to this being a category. This is useful if this library
|
|
|
|
|
is later extended to talk about higher categories.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\section{Product}
|
2018-04-24 12:11:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
In the following I'll demonstrate a technique for using categories to prove
|
|
|
|
|
properties. The goal in this section is to show that products are propositions:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
\prod_{\bC \tp \Category} \prod_{A\;B \tp \Object} \isProp\ (\mathit{Product}\ \bC\ A\ B)
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
Where $\mathit{Product}\ \bC\ A\ B$ denotes the type of products of objects $A$
|
|
|
|
|
and $B$ in the category $\bC$. I do this by constructing a category whose
|
|
|
|
|
terminal objects are equivalent to products in $\bC$, and since terminal objects
|
|
|
|
|
are propositional in a proper category and equivalences preservehomotopy level,
|
|
|
|
|
then we know that products also are propositions. But before we get to that,
|
|
|
|
|
let's recall the definition of products.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Given a category $\bC$ and two objects $A$ and $B$ in $bC$ we define the product
|
|
|
|
|
of $A$ and $B$ to be an object $A \x B$ in $\bC$ and two arrows $\pi_1 \tp A \x
|
|
|
|
|
B \to A$ and $\pi_2 \tp A \x B \to B$ called the projections of the product. The projections must satisfy the following property:
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
For all $X \tp Object$, $f \tp \Arrow\ X\ A$ and $g \tp \Arrow\ X\ B$ we have
|
|
|
|
|
that there exists a unique arrow $\pi \tp \Arrow\ X\ (A \x B)$ satisfying
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align}
|
|
|
|
|
\label{eq:umpProduct}
|
|
|
|
|
%% \prod_{X \tp Object} \prod_{f \tp \Arrow\ X\ A} \prod_{g \tp \Arrow\ X\ B}\\
|
|
|
|
|
%% \uexists_{f \x g \tp \Arrow\ X\ (A \x B)}
|
|
|
|
|
\pi_1 \lll \pi \equiv f \x \pi_2 \lll \pi \equiv g
|
|
|
|
|
%% ump : ∀ {X : Object} (f : ℂ [ X , A ]) (g : ℂ [ X , B ])
|
|
|
|
|
%% → ∃![ f×g ] (ℂ [ fst ∘ f×g ] ≡ f P.× ℂ [ snd ∘ f×g ] ≡ g)
|
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
$
|
|
|
|
|
$\pi$ is called the product (arrow) of $f$ and $g$.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
2018-04-23 15:06:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\section{Monads}
|
2018-04-09 16:02:54 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% \subsubsection{Functors}
|
|
|
|
|
%% Defines the notion of a functor - also split up into data and laws.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% Propositionality for being a functor.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% Composition of functors and the identity functor.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% \subsubsection{Products}
|
|
|
|
|
%% Definition of what it means for an object to be a product in a given category.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% Definition of what it means for a category to have all products.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% \WIP{} Prove propositionality for being a product and having products.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% \subsubsection{Exponentials}
|
|
|
|
|
%% Definition of what it means to be an exponential object.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% Definition of what it means for a category to have all exponential objects.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% \subsubsection{Cartesian closed categories}
|
|
|
|
|
%% Definition of what it means for a category to be cartesian closed; namely that
|
|
|
|
|
%% it has all products and all exponentials.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% \subsubsection{Natural transformations}
|
|
|
|
|
%% Definition of transformations\footnote{Maybe this is a name I made up for a
|
|
|
|
|
%% family of morphisms} and the naturality condition for these.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% Proof that naturality is a mere proposition and the accompanying equality
|
|
|
|
|
%% principle. Proof that natural transformations are homotopic sets.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% The identity natural transformation.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% \subsubsection{Yoneda embedding}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% The yoneda embedding is typically presented in terms of the category of
|
|
|
|
|
%% categories (cf. Awodey) \emph however this is not stricly needed - all we need
|
|
|
|
|
%% is what would be the exponential object in that category - this happens to be
|
|
|
|
|
%% functors and so this is how we define the yoneda embedding.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% \subsubsection{Monads}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% Defines an equivalence between these two formulations of a monad:
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% \subsubsubsection{Monoidal monads}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% Defines the standard monoidal representation of a monad:
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% An endofunctor with two natural transformations (called ``pure'' and ``join'')
|
|
|
|
|
%% and some laws about these natural transformations.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% Propositionality proofs and equality principle is provided.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% \subsubsubsection{Kleisli monads}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% A presentation of monads perhaps more familiar to a functional programer:
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% A map on objects and two maps on morphisms (called ``pure'' and ``bind'') and
|
|
|
|
|
%% some laws about these maps.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% Propositionality proofs and equality principle is provided.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% \subsubsubsection{Voevodsky's construction}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% Provides construction 2.3 as presented in an unpublished paper by Vladimir
|
|
|
|
|
%% Voevodsky. This construction is similiar to the equivalence provided for the two
|
|
|
|
|
%% preceding formulations
|
|
|
|
|
%% \footnote{ TODO: I would like to include in the thesis some motivation for why
|
|
|
|
|
%% this construction is particularly interesting.}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% \subsubsection{Functors}
|
|
|
|
|
%% The category of functors and natural transformations. An immediate corrolary is
|
|
|
|
|
%% the set of presheaf categories.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% \WIP{} I have not shown that the category of functors is univalent.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% \subsubsection{Relations}
|
|
|
|
|
%% The category of relations. \WIP{} I have not shown that this category is
|
|
|
|
|
%% univalent. Not sure I intend to do so either.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% \subsubsection{Free category}
|
|
|
|
|
%% The free category of a category. \WIP{} I have not shown that this category is
|
|
|
|
|
%% univalent.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% \subsection{Current Challenges}
|
|
|
|
|
%% Besides the items marked \WIP{} above I still feel a bit unsure about what to
|
|
|
|
|
%% include in my report. Most of my work so far has been specifically about
|
|
|
|
|
%% developing this library. Some ideas:
|
|
|
|
|
%% %
|
|
|
|
|
%% \begin{itemize}
|
|
|
|
|
%% \item
|
|
|
|
|
%% Modularity properties
|
|
|
|
|
%% \item
|
|
|
|
|
%% Compare with setoid-approach to solve similiar problems.
|
|
|
|
|
%% \item
|
|
|
|
|
%% How to structure an implementation to best deal with types that have no
|
|
|
|
|
%% structure (propositions) and those that do (sets and everything above)
|
|
|
|
|
%% \end{itemize}
|
|
|
|
|
%% %
|
|
|
|
|
%% \subsection{Ideas for future developments}
|
|
|
|
|
%% \subsubsection{Higher categories}
|
|
|
|
|
%% I only have a notion of (1-)categories. Perhaps it would be nice to also
|
|
|
|
|
%% formalize higher categories.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% \subsubsection{Hierarchy of concepts related to monads}
|
|
|
|
|
%% In Haskell the type-class Monad sits in a hierarchy atop the notion of a functor
|
|
|
|
|
%% and applicative functors. There's probably a similiar notion in the
|
|
|
|
|
%% category-theoretic approach to developing this.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% As I have already defined monads from these two perspectives, it would be
|
|
|
|
|
%% interesting to take this idea even further and actually show how monads are
|
|
|
|
|
%% related to applicative functors and functors. I'm not entirely sure how this
|
|
|
|
|
%% would look in Agda though.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
%% \subsubsection{Use formulation on the standard library}
|
|
|
|
|
%% I also thought it would be interesting to use this library to show certain
|
|
|
|
|
%% properties about functors, applicative functors and monads used in the Agda
|
|
|
|
|
%% Standard library. So I went ahead and tried to show that agda's standard
|
|
|
|
|
%% library's notion of a functor (along with suitable laws) is equivalent to my
|
|
|
|
|
%% formulation (in the category of homotopic sets). I ran into two problems here,
|
|
|
|
|
%% however; the first one is that the standard library's notion of a functor is
|
|
|
|
|
%% indexed by the object map:
|
|
|
|
|
%% %
|
|
|
|
|
%% $$
|
|
|
|
|
%% \Functor \tp (\Type \to \Type) \to \Type
|
|
|
|
|
%% $$
|
|
|
|
|
%% %
|
|
|
|
|
%% Where $\Functor\ F$ has the member:
|
|
|
|
|
%% %
|
|
|
|
|
%% $$
|
|
|
|
|
%% \fmap \tp (A \to B) \to F A \to F B
|
|
|
|
|
%% $$
|
|
|
|
|
%% %
|
|
|
|
|
%% Whereas the object map in my definition is existentially quantified:
|
|
|
|
|
%% %
|
|
|
|
|
%% $$
|
|
|
|
|
%% \Functor \tp \Type
|
|
|
|
|
%% $$
|
|
|
|
|
%% %
|
|
|
|
|
%% And $\Functor$ has these members:
|
|
|
|
|
%% \begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
%% F & \tp \Type \to \Type \\
|
|
|
|
|
%% \fmap & \tp (A \to B) \to F A \to F B\}
|
|
|
|
|
%% \end{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
%% %
|