2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\chapter{Cubical Agda}
|
|
|
|
|
\section{Propositional equality}
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
Judgmental equality in Agda is a feature of the type system. It is
|
|
|
|
|
something that can be checked automatically by the type checker: In
|
|
|
|
|
the example from the introduction $n + 0$ can be judged to be equal to
|
|
|
|
|
$n$ simply by expanding the definition of $+$.
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
On the other hand, propositional equality is something defined within
|
|
|
|
|
the language itself. Propositional equality cannot be derived
|
2018-07-17 14:51:16 +00:00
|
|
|
|
automatically. The normal definition of propositional equality is an
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
inductive data type. Cubical Agda discards this type in favor of some
|
|
|
|
|
new primitives.
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
Most of the source code related with this section is implemented in
|
|
|
|
|
\cite{cubical-demo} it can be browsed in hyperlinked and syntax
|
|
|
|
|
highlighted HTML online. The links can be found in the beginning of
|
|
|
|
|
section \S\ref{ch:implementation}.
|
2018-05-08 14:22:51 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\subsection{The equality type}
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
The usual notion of judgmental equality says that given a type $A \tp
|
|
|
|
|
\MCU$ and two points hereof $a_0, a_1 \tp A$ we can form the type:
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align}
|
|
|
|
|
a_0 \equiv a_1 \tp \MCU
|
|
|
|
|
\end{align}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
In Agda this is defined as an inductive data type with the single
|
|
|
|
|
constructor $\refl$ that for any $a \tp A$ gives:
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align}
|
|
|
|
|
\refl \tp a \equiv a
|
|
|
|
|
\end{align}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-09 16:13:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
There also exist a related notion of \emph{heterogeneous} equality which allows
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
for equating points of different types. In this case given two types $A, B \tp
|
|
|
|
|
\MCU$ and two points $a \tp A$, $b \tp B$ we can construct the type:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align}
|
|
|
|
|
a \cong b \tp \MCU
|
|
|
|
|
\end{align}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
This likewise has the single constructor $\refl$ that for any $a \tp
|
|
|
|
|
A$ gives:
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align}
|
|
|
|
|
\refl \tp a \cong a
|
|
|
|
|
\end{align}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
In Cubical Agda these two notions are paralleled with homogeneous- and
|
|
|
|
|
heterogeneous paths respectively.
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\subsection{The path type}
|
2018-05-09 16:13:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
Judgmental equality in Cubical Agda is encapsulated with the type:
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-09 16:13:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\begin{equation}
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\Path \tp (P \tp \I → \MCU) → P\ 0 → P\ 1 → \MCU
|
2018-05-09 16:13:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\end{equation}
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
The special type $\I$ is called the index set. The index set can be
|
|
|
|
|
thought of simply as the interval on the real numbers from $0$ to $1$
|
|
|
|
|
(both inclusive). The family $P$ over $\I$ will be referred to as the
|
|
|
|
|
\nomenindex{path space} given some path $p \tp \Path\ P\ a\ b$. By
|
|
|
|
|
that token $P\ 0$ corresponds to the type at the left endpoint of $p$.
|
|
|
|
|
Likewise $P\ 1$ is the type at the right endpoint. The type is called
|
|
|
|
|
$\Path$ because the idea has roots in homotopy theory. The intuition
|
|
|
|
|
is that $\Path$ describes\linebreak[1] paths in $\MCU$. I.e.\ paths
|
|
|
|
|
between types. For a path $p$ the expression $p\ i$ can be thought of
|
|
|
|
|
as a \emph{point} on this path. The index $i$ describes how far along
|
|
|
|
|
the path one has moved. An inhabitant of $\Path\ P\ a_0\ a_1$ is a
|
|
|
|
|
(dependent) function from the index set to the path space:
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
p \tp \prod_{i \tp \I} P\ i
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-07-17 14:51:16 +00:00
|
|
|
|
This function must satisfy being judgmentally equal to $a_0$ at the
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
left endpoint and equal to $a_1$ at the other end. I.e.:
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
p\ 0 & = a_0 \\
|
|
|
|
|
p\ 1 & = a_1
|
2018-05-07 08:53:22 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-15 14:08:29 +00:00
|
|
|
|
The notion of \nomenindex{homogeneous equalities} is recovered when $P$ does not
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
depend on its argument. That is for $A \tp \MCU$ and $a_0, a_1 \tp A$ the
|
2018-05-15 14:08:29 +00:00
|
|
|
|
homogenous equality between $a_0$ and $a_1$ is the type:
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
a_0 \equiv a_1 \defeq \Path\ (\lambda\;i \to A)\ a_0\ a_1
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
I will generally prefer to use the notation $a \equiv b$ when talking
|
|
|
|
|
about non-dependent paths and use the notation $\Path\ (\lambda\; i
|
|
|
|
|
\to P\ i)\ a\ b$ when the path space is of particular interest.
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
2018-07-17 14:51:16 +00:00
|
|
|
|
With this definition we can recover reflexivity. That is, for any $A
|
|
|
|
|
\tp \MCU$ and $a \tp A$:
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-08 00:00:23 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\begin{equation}
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{aligned}
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\refl & \tp a \equiv a \\
|
|
|
|
|
\refl & \defeq \lambda\; i \to a
|
2018-05-08 00:00:23 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\end{aligned}
|
|
|
|
|
\end{equation}
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
Here the path space is $P \defeq \lambda\; i \to A$ and it satsifies
|
|
|
|
|
$P\ i = A$ definitionally. So to inhabit it, is to give a path $\I \to
|
2018-07-17 14:51:16 +00:00
|
|
|
|
A$ that is judgmentally $a$ at either endpoint. This is satisfied by
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
the constant path; i.e.\ the path that is constantly $a$ at any index
|
|
|
|
|
$i \tp \I$.
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
It is also surprisingly easy to show functional extensionality.
|
|
|
|
|
Functional extensionality is the proposition that given a type $A \tp
|
|
|
|
|
\MCU$, a family of types $B \tp A \to \MCU$ and functions $f, g \tp
|
|
|
|
|
\prod_{a \tp A} B\ a$ gives:
|
2018-05-09 16:13:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{equation}
|
|
|
|
|
\label{eq:funExt}
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\funExt \tp \left(\prod_{a \tp A} f\ a \equiv g\ a \right) \to f \equiv g
|
2018-05-09 16:13:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\end{equation}
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%% p = λ\; i a → p a i
|
2018-07-17 14:51:16 +00:00
|
|
|
|
So given $η \tp \prod_{a \tp A} f\ a \equiv g\ a$ we must give a path
|
|
|
|
|
$f \equiv g$. That is a function $\I \to \prod_{a \tp A} B\ a$. So let
|
|
|
|
|
$i \tp \I$ be given. We must now give an expression $\phi \tp
|
|
|
|
|
\prod_{a \tp A} B\ a$ satisfying $\phi\ 0 \equiv f\ a$ and $\phi\ 1
|
|
|
|
|
\equiv g\ a$. This neccesitates that the expression must be a lambda
|
|
|
|
|
abstraction, so let $a \tp A$ be given. We can now apply $a$ to $η$
|
|
|
|
|
and get the path $η\ a \tp f\ a \equiv g\ a$. This exactly
|
|
|
|
|
satisfies the conditions for $\phi$. In conclusion \ref{eq:funExt} is
|
|
|
|
|
inhabited by the term:
|
2018-05-09 16:13:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\begin{equation*}
|
|
|
|
|
\funExt\ η \defeq λ\; i\ a → η\ a\ i
|
|
|
|
|
\end{equation*}
|
2018-05-09 16:13:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
With $\funExt$ in place we can now construct a path between
|
|
|
|
|
$\var{zeroLeft}$ and $\var{zeroRight}$ -- the functions defined in the
|
|
|
|
|
introduction \S\ref{sec:functional-extensionality}:
|
2018-05-09 16:13:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
p & \tp \var{zeroLeft} \equiv \var{zeroRight} \\
|
|
|
|
|
p & \defeq \funExt\ \var{zrn}
|
2018-05-09 16:13:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
Here $\var{zrn}$ is the proof from \ref{eq:zrn}.
|
2018-05-15 14:08:29 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\section{Homotopy levels}
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
In ITT all equality proofs are identical (in a closed context). This
|
|
|
|
|
means that, in some sense, any two inhabitants of $a \equiv b$ are
|
|
|
|
|
``equally good''. They do not have any interesting structure. This is
|
|
|
|
|
referred to as Uniqueness of Identity Proofs (UIP). Unfortunately it
|
2018-07-17 14:51:16 +00:00
|
|
|
|
is not possible to have a type theory with both univalence and UIP.
|
|
|
|
|
Instead in cubical Agda we have a hierarchy of types with an
|
|
|
|
|
increasing amount of homotopic structure. At the bottom of this
|
|
|
|
|
hierarchy is the set of contractible types:
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{equation}
|
2018-05-08 00:00:23 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\begin{aligned}
|
|
|
|
|
%% \begin{split}
|
2018-05-09 16:13:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
& \isContr && \tp \MCU \to \MCU \\
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
& \isContr\ A && \defeq \sum_{c \tp A} \prod_{a \tp A} a \equiv c
|
2018-05-08 00:00:23 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%% \end{split}
|
|
|
|
|
\end{aligned}
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\end{equation}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
The first component of $\isContr\ A$ is called ``the center of contraction''.
|
2018-05-15 14:08:29 +00:00
|
|
|
|
Under the propositions-as-types interpretation of type theory $\isContr\ A$ can
|
2018-05-09 16:13:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
be thought of as ``the true proposition $A$''. And indeed $\top$ is
|
|
|
|
|
contractible:
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-09 16:13:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\begin{equation*}
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
(\var{tt} , \lambda\; x \to \refl) \tp \isContr\ \top
|
2018-05-09 16:13:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\end{equation*}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
It is a theorem that if a type is contractible, then it is isomorphic to the
|
|
|
|
|
unit-type.
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
The next step in the hierarchy is the set of mere propositions:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{equation}
|
2018-05-08 00:00:23 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\begin{aligned}
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
& \isProp && \tp \MCU \to \MCU \\
|
|
|
|
|
& \isProp\ A && \defeq \prod_{a_0, a_1 \tp A} a_0 \equiv a_1
|
2018-05-08 00:00:23 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\end{aligned}
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\end{equation}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-15 14:08:29 +00:00
|
|
|
|
One can think of $\isProp\ A$ as the set of true and false propositions. And
|
2018-05-09 16:13:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
indeed both $\top$ and $\bot$ are propositions:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
(λ\; \var{tt}, \var{tt} → refl) & \tp \isProp\ ⊤ \\
|
|
|
|
|
λ\;\varnothing\ \varnothing & \tp \isProp\ ⊥
|
2018-05-09 16:13:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-15 14:08:29 +00:00
|
|
|
|
The term $\varnothing$ is used here to denote an impossible pattern. It is a
|
|
|
|
|
theorem that if a mere proposition $A$ is inhabited, then so is it contractible.
|
|
|
|
|
If it is not inhabited it is equivalent to the empty-type (or false
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
proposition).
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
I will refer to a type $A \tp \MCU$ as a \emph{mere proposition} if I want to
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
stress that we have $\isProp\ A$.
|
|
|
|
|
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
The next step in the hierarchy is the set of homotopical sets:
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{equation}
|
2018-05-08 00:00:23 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\begin{aligned}
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
& \isSet && \tp \MCU \to \MCU \\
|
|
|
|
|
& \isSet\ A && \defeq \prod_{a_0, a_1 \tp A} \isProp\ (a_0 \equiv a_1)
|
2018-05-08 00:00:23 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\end{aligned}
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\end{equation}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
I will not give an example of a set at this point. It turns out that
|
|
|
|
|
proving e.g.\ $\isProp\ \bN$ directly is not so straightforward (see
|
|
|
|
|
\cite[\S3.1.4]{hott-2013}). Hedberg's theorem states that any type
|
|
|
|
|
with decidable equality is a set. There will be examples of sets later
|
|
|
|
|
in this report. At this point it should be noted that the term ``set''
|
2018-07-17 14:51:16 +00:00
|
|
|
|
is somewhat conflated; there is the notion of sets from set theory.
|
|
|
|
|
In Agda types are denoted \texttt{Set}. I will use it consistently to
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
refer to a type $A$ as a set exactly if $\isSet\ A$ is a proposition.
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
2018-05-09 16:47:12 +00:00
|
|
|
|
As the reader may have guessed the next step in the hierarchy is the type:
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{equation}
|
2018-05-08 00:00:23 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\begin{aligned}
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
& \isGroupoid && \tp \MCU \to \MCU \\
|
|
|
|
|
& \isGroupoid\ A && \defeq \prod_{a_0, a_1 \tp A} \isSet\ (a_0 \equiv a_1)
|
2018-05-08 00:00:23 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\end{aligned}
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\end{equation}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-07-17 14:51:16 +00:00
|
|
|
|
So it continues. In fact we can generalize this family of types by
|
|
|
|
|
indexing them with a natural number. For historical reasons, though,
|
|
|
|
|
the bottom of the hierarchy, the contractible types, is said to be a
|
|
|
|
|
\nomen{-2-type}{homotopy levels}, propositions are
|
|
|
|
|
\nomen{-1-types}{homotopy levels}, (homotopical) sets are
|
|
|
|
|
\nomen{0-types}{homotopy levels} and so on\ldots
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Just as with paths, homotopical sets are not at the center of focus for this
|
|
|
|
|
thesis. But I mention here some properties that will be relevant for this
|
|
|
|
|
exposition:
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Proposition: Homotopy levels are cumulative. That is, if $A \tp \MCU$ has
|
|
|
|
|
homotopy level $n$ then so does it have $n + 1$.
|
|
|
|
|
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
For any level $n$ it is the case that to be of level $n$ is a mere proposition.
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\section{A few lemmas}
|
2018-05-23 16:28:27 +00:00
|
|
|
|
Rather than getting into the nitty-gritty details of Agda I venture to
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
take a more ``combinator-based'' approach. That is I will use
|
|
|
|
|
theorems about paths that have already been formalized.
|
2018-05-23 16:28:27 +00:00
|
|
|
|
Specifically the results come from the Agda library \texttt{cubical}
|
|
|
|
|
(\cite{cubical-demo}). I have used a handful of results from this
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
library as well as contributed a few lemmas myself%
|
|
|
|
|
\footnote{The module \texttt{Cat.Prelude} lists the upstream
|
2018-07-17 14:51:16 +00:00
|
|
|
|
dependencies. My contribution to \texttt{cubical} can as well be
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
found in the git logs which are available at
|
|
|
|
|
\hrefsymb{https://github.com/Saizan/cubical-demo}{\texttt{https://github.com/Saizan/cubical-demo}}.
|
|
|
|
|
}.
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
These theorems are all purely related to homotopy type theory and as
|
|
|
|
|
such not specific to the formalization of Category Theory. I will
|
|
|
|
|
present a few of these theorems here as they will be used throughout
|
|
|
|
|
chapter \ref{ch:implementation}. They should also give the reader some
|
|
|
|
|
intuition about the path type.
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\subsection{Path induction}
|
2018-05-03 12:18:51 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\label{sec:pathJ}
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
The induction principle for paths intuitively gives us a way to reason
|
|
|
|
|
about a type family indexed by a path by only considering if said path
|
|
|
|
|
is $\refl$ (the \nomen{base case}{path induction}). For \emph{based
|
|
|
|
|
path induction}, that equality is \emph{based} at some element $a
|
|
|
|
|
\tp A$.
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\pagebreak[3]
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{samepage}
|
|
|
|
|
Let a type $A \tp \MCU$ and an element of the type $a \tp A$ be
|
|
|
|
|
given. $a$ is said to be the base of the induction.\linebreak[3] Given
|
|
|
|
|
a family of types:
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-05-10 13:28:33 +00:00
|
|
|
|
D \tp \prod_{b \tp A} \prod_{p \tp a ≡ b} \MCU
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-07-17 14:51:16 +00:00
|
|
|
|
and an inhabitant of $D$ at $\refl$:
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-05-10 13:28:33 +00:00
|
|
|
|
d \tp D\ a\ \refl
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
We have the function:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-09 16:13:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\begin{equation}
|
2018-05-18 11:14:41 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\pathJ\ D\ d \tp \prod_{b \tp A} \prod_{p \tp a ≡ b} D\ b\ p
|
2018-05-09 16:13:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\end{equation}
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\end{samepage}%
|
|
|
|
|
|
2018-05-10 13:28:33 +00:00
|
|
|
|
A simple application of $\pathJ$ is for proving that $\var{sym}$ is an
|
|
|
|
|
involution. Namely for any set $A \tp \MCU$, points $a, b \tp A$ and a path
|
|
|
|
|
between them $p \tp a \equiv b$:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{equation}
|
|
|
|
|
\label{eq:sym-invol}
|
|
|
|
|
\var{sym}\ (\var{sym}\ p) ≡ p
|
|
|
|
|
\end{equation}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
The proof will be by induction on $p$ and will be based at $a$. That
|
|
|
|
|
is $D$ will be the family:
|
2018-05-10 13:28:33 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
2018-05-11 11:07:47 +00:00
|
|
|
|
D & \tp \prod_{b' \tp A} \prod_{p \tp a ≡ b'} \MCU \\
|
2018-05-10 13:28:33 +00:00
|
|
|
|
D\ b'\ p' & \defeq \var{sym}\ (\var{sym}\ p') ≡ p'
|
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-15 14:08:29 +00:00
|
|
|
|
The base case will then be:
|
2018-05-10 13:28:33 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
d & \tp \var{sym}\ (\var{sym}\ \refl) ≡ \refl \\
|
|
|
|
|
d & \defeq \refl
|
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
The reason $\refl$ proves this is that $\var{sym}\ \refl = \refl$ holds
|
|
|
|
|
definitionally. In summary \ref{eq:sym-invol} is inhabited by the term:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
2018-05-11 11:07:47 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\pathJ\ D\ d\ b\ p
|
2018-05-10 13:28:33 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\tp
|
|
|
|
|
\var{sym}\ (\var{sym}\ p) ≡ p
|
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-11 11:07:47 +00:00
|
|
|
|
Another application of $\pathJ$ is for proving associativity of $\trans$. That
|
|
|
|
|
is, given a type $A \tp \MCU$, elements of $A$, $a, b, c, d \tp A$ and paths
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
between them $p \tp a \equiv b$, $q \tp b \equiv c$ and $r \tp c \equiv d$ we
|
2018-05-11 11:07:47 +00:00
|
|
|
|
have the following:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{equation}
|
|
|
|
|
\label{eq:cum-trans}
|
|
|
|
|
\trans\ p\ (\trans\ q\ r) ≡ \trans\ (\trans\ p\ q)\ r
|
|
|
|
|
\end{equation}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
In this case the induction will be based at $c$ (the left-endpoint of $r$) and
|
|
|
|
|
over the family:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
T & \tp \prod_{d' \tp A} \prod_{r' \tp c ≡ d'} \MCU \\
|
|
|
|
|
T\ d'\ r' & \defeq \trans\ p\ (\trans\ q\ r') ≡ \trans\ (\trans\ p\ q)\ r'
|
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-07-17 14:51:16 +00:00
|
|
|
|
The base case is proven with $t$ which is defined as:
|
2018-05-11 11:07:47 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
\trans\ p\ (\trans\ q\ \refl) & ≡
|
|
|
|
|
\trans\ p\ q \\
|
|
|
|
|
& ≡
|
|
|
|
|
\trans\ (\trans\ p\ q)\ \refl
|
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
Here we have used the proposition $\trans\ p\ \refl \equiv p$ without proof. In
|
|
|
|
|
conclusion \ref{eq:cum-trans} is inhabited by the term:
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
\pathJ\ T\ t\ d\ r
|
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
We shall see another application of path induction in \ref{eq:pathJ-example}.
|
2018-05-09 16:13:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\subsection{Paths over propositions}
|
2018-05-03 12:18:51 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\label{sec:lemPropF}
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
Another very useful combinator is $\lemPropF$: Given a type $A \tp
|
|
|
|
|
\MCU$ and a type family on $A$; $D \tp A \to \MCU$. Let $\var{propD}
|
|
|
|
|
\tp \prod_{x \tp A} \isProp\ (D\ x)$ be the proof that $D$ is a mere
|
|
|
|
|
proposition for all elements of $A$. Furthermore say we have a path
|
|
|
|
|
between some two elements in $A$; $p \tp a_0 \equiv a_1$ then we can
|
|
|
|
|
built a heterogeneous path between any two elements of $d_0 \tp
|
|
|
|
|
D\ a_0$ and $d_1 \tp D\ a_1$.
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\lemPropF\ \var{propD}\ p \tp \Path\ (\lambda\; i \mto D\ (p\ i))\ d_0\ d_1
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
Note that $d_0$ and $d_1$, though points of the same family, have
|
2018-07-17 14:51:16 +00:00
|
|
|
|
different types. This is quite a mouthful, so let me try to show how
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
this is a very general and useful result.
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Often when proving equalities between elements of some dependent types
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$\lemPropF$ can be used to boil this complexity down to showing that
|
|
|
|
|
the dependent parts of the type are mere propositions. For instance
|
|
|
|
|
say we have a type:
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
T \defeq \sum_{a \tp A} D\ a
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-07-17 14:51:16 +00:00
|
|
|
|
for some proposition $D \tp A \to \MCU$. That is we have $\var{propD}
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\tp \prod_{a \tp A} \isProp\ (D\ a)$. If we want to prove $t_0 \equiv
|
|
|
|
|
t_1$ for two elements $t_0, t_1 \tp T$ then this will be a pair of
|
|
|
|
|
paths:
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
p \tp & \fst\ t_0 \equiv \fst\ t_1 \\
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
& \Path\ (\lambda\; i \to D\ (p\ i))\ (\snd\ t_0)\ (\snd\ t_1)
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
Here $\lemPropF$ directly allow us to prove the latter of these given
|
|
|
|
|
that we have already provided $p$.
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\lemPropF\ \var{propD}\ p
|
|
|
|
|
\tp \Path\ (\lambda\; i \to D\ (p\ i))\ (\snd\ t_0)\ (\snd\ t_1)
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
\subsection{Functions over propositions}
|
2018-07-17 14:51:16 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\label{sec:propPi}%
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$\prod$-types preserve propositionality when the co-domain is always a
|
|
|
|
|
proposition.
|
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
\mathit{propPi} \tp \left(\prod_{a \tp A} \isProp\ (P\ a)\right) \to \isProp\ \left(\prod_{a \tp A} P\ a\right)
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
\subsection{Pairs over propositions}
|
2018-05-03 12:18:51 +00:00
|
|
|
|
\label{sec:propSig}
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
$\sum$-types preserve propositionality whenever its first component is
|
2018-07-17 14:51:16 +00:00
|
|
|
|
a proposition and its second component is a proposition for all
|
2018-05-28 15:32:56 +00:00
|
|
|
|
points of the left type.
|
2018-05-02 15:02:46 +00:00
|
|
|
|
%
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|
|
|
|
|
\mathit{propSig} \tp \isProp\ A \to \left(\prod_{a \tp A} \isProp\ (P\ a)\right) \to \isProp\ \left(\sum_{a \tp A} P\ a\right)
|
|
|
|
|
$$
|